A homogeneous history is a sequence of Propositions specified at different moments of time . We write this as: and read it as "the proposition is true at time and then the proposition is true at time and then ". The times are strictly ordered and called the temporal support of the history. Inhomogeneous histories are multiple-time propositions which cannot be represented by a homogeneous history. An example is the logical OR of two homogeneous histories:. These propositions can correspond to any set of questions that include all possibilities. Examples might be the three propositions meaning "the electron went through the left slit", "the electron went through the right slit" and "the electron didn't go through either slit". One of the aims of the theory is to show that classical questions such as, "where are my keys?" are consistent. In this case one might use a large number of propositions each one specifying the location of the keys in some small region of space. Each single-time proposition can be represented by a projection operator acting on the system's Hilbert space. It is then useful to represent homogeneous histories by the time-ordered product of their single-time projection operators. This is the history projection operator formalism developed by Christopher Isham and naturally encodes the logical structure of the history propositions.
Consistency
An important construction in the consistent histories approach is the class operator for a homogeneous history: The symbol indicates that the factors in the product are ordered chronologically according to their values of : the "past" operators with smaller values of appear on the right side, and the "future" operators with greater values of appear on the left side. This definition can be extended to inhomogeneous histories as well. Central to the consistent histories is the notion of consistency. A set of histories is consistent if for all. Here represents the initial density matrix, and the operators are expressed in the Heisenberg picture. The set of histories is weakly consistent if for all.
Probabilities
If a set of histories is consistent then probabilities can be assigned to them in a consistent way. We postulate that the probability of history is simply which obeys the axioms of probability if the histories come from the same consistent set. As an example, this means the probability of " OR " equals the probability of "" plus the probability of "" minus the probability of " AND ", and so forth.
Interpretation
The interpretation based on consistent histories is used in combination with the insights about quantum decoherence. Quantum decoherence implies that irreversible macroscopic phenomena render histories automatically consistent, which allows one to recover classical reasoning and "common sense" when applied to the outcomes of these measurements. More precise analysis of decoherence allows a quantitative calculation of the boundary between the classical domain and the quantum domain covariance. According to Roland Omnès, In order to obtain a complete theory, the formal rules above must be supplemented with a particular Hilbert space and rules that govern dynamics, for example a Hamiltonian. In the opinion of others this still does not make a complete theory as no predictions are possible about which set of consistent histories will actually occur. That is the rules of consistent histories, the Hilbert space, and the Hamiltonian must be supplemented by a set selection rule. However, Griffiths holds the opinion that asking the question of which set of histories will "actually occur" is a misinterpretation of the theory; histories are a tool for description of reality, not separate alternate realities. Proponents of this consistent histories interpretation—such as Murray Gell-Mann, James Hartle, Roland Omnès and Robert B. Griffiths—argue that their interpretation clarifies the fundamental disadvantages of the old Copenhagen interpretation, and can be used as a complete interpretational framework for quantum mechanics. In Quantum Philosophy, Roland Omnès provides a less mathematical way of understanding this same formalism. The consistent histories approach can be interpreted as a way of understanding which properties of a quantum system can be treated in a single framework, and which properties must be treated in different frameworks and would produce meaningless results if combined as if they belonged to a single framework. It thus becomes possible to demonstrate formally why it is that the properties which J. S. Bell assumed could be combined together, cannot. On the other hand, it also becomes possible to demonstrate that classical, logical reasoning does apply, even to quantum experiments – but we can now be mathematically exact about how such reasoning applies.