The term differential is used in calculus to refer to an infinitesimal change in some varying quantity. For example, if x is a variable, then a change in the value of x is often denoted Δx. The differential dx represents an infinitely small change in the variable x. The idea of an infinitely small or infinitely slow change is, intuitively, extremely useful, and there are a number of ways to make the notion mathematically precise. Using calculus, it is possible to relate the infinitely small changes of various variables to each other mathematically using derivatives. If y is a function of x, then the differential dy of y is related to dx by the formula where dy/dx denotes the derivative of y with respect to x. This formula summarizes the intuitive idea that the derivative of y with respect to x is the limit of the ratio of differences Δy/Δx as Δx becomes infinitesimal. There are several approaches for making the notion of differentials mathematically precise.
Differentials in smooth models of set theory. This approach is known as synthetic differential geometry or smooth infinitesimal analysis and is closely related to the algebraic geometric approach, except that ideas from topos theory are used to hide the mechanisms by which nilpotent infinitesimals are introduced.
These approaches are very different from each other, but they have in common the idea of being quantitative, i.e., saying not just that a differential is infinitely small, but how small it is.
History and usage
quantities played a significant role in the development of calculus. Archimedes used them, even though he didn't believe that arguments involving infinitesimals were rigorous. Isaac Newton referred to them as fluxions. However, it was Gottfried Leibniz who coined the term differentials for infinitesimal quantities and introduced the notation for them which is still used today. In Leibniz's notation, if x is a variable quantity, then dx denotes an infinitesimal change in the variable x. Thus, if y is a function of x, then the derivative of y with respect to x is often denoted dy/dx, which would otherwise be denoted ẏ or y. The use of differentials in this form attracted much criticism, for instance in the famous pamphlet The Analyst by Bishop Berkeley. Nevertheless, the notation has remained popular because it suggests strongly the idea that the derivative of y at x is its instantaneous rate of change, which may be obtained by taking the limit of the ratio Δy/Δx of the change in y over the change in x, as the change in x becomes arbitrarily small. Differentials are also compatible with dimensional analysis, where a differential such as dx has the same dimensions as the variable x. Differentials are also used in the notation for integrals because an integral can be regarded as an infinite sum of infinitesimal quantities: the area under a graph is obtained by subdividing the graph into infinitely thin strips and summing their areas. In an expression such as the integral sign denotes the infinite sum, f denotes the "height" of a thin strip, and the differential dx denotes its infinitely thin width.
Differentials as linear maps
There is a simple way to make precise sense of differentials by regarding them as linear maps. To illustrate, suppose f is a real-valued function on R. We can reinterpret the variable x in f as being a function rather than a number, namely the identity map on the real line, which takes a real numberp to itself: x = p. Then f is the composite of f with x, whose value at p is f = f. The differential df is then a function whose value at p is not a number, but a linear map from R to R. Since a linear map from R to R is given by a 1×1 matrix, it is essentially the same thing as a number, but the change in the point of view allows us to think of dfp as an infinitesimal and compare it with the standard infinitesimaldxp, which is again just the identity map from R to R. The identity map has the property that if ε is very small, then dxp is very small, which enables us to regard it as infinitesimal. The differential dfp has the same property, because it is just a multiple of dxp, and this multiple is the derivative f ′ by definition. We therefore obtain that dfp = f ′ dxp, and hence df = f ′ dx. Thus we recover the idea that f ′ is the ratio of the differentials df and dx. This would just be a trick were it not for the fact that:
it captures the idea of the derivative of f at p as the best linear approximation to f at p;
it has many generalizations.
For instance, if f is a function from Rn to R, then we say that f is differentiable at p ∈ Rn if there is a linear map dfp from Rn to R such that for any ε > 0, there is a neighbourhoodN of p such that for x ∈ N, We can now use the same trick as in the one-dimensional case and think of the expression f as the composite of f with the standard coordinates x1, x2,..., xn on Rn. Then the differentials p, p, p at a point p form a basis for the vector space of linear maps from Rn to R and therefore, if f is differentiable at p, we can write dfp as a linear combination of these basis elements: The coefficients Djf are the partial derivatives of f at p with respect to x1, x2,..., xn. Hence, if f is differentiable on all of Rn, we can write, more concisely: In the one-dimensional case this becomes as before. This idea generalizes straightforwardly to functions from Rn to Rm. Furthermore, it has the decisive advantage over other definitions of the derivative that it is invariant under changes of coordinates. This means that the same idea can be used to define the differential of smooth maps between smooth manifolds. Aside: Note that the existence of all the partial derivatives of f at x is a necessary condition for the existence of a differential at x. However it is not a sufficient condition. For counterexamples, see Gateaux derivative.
Algebraic geometry
In algebraic geometry, differentials and other infinitesimal notions are handled in a very explicit way by accepting that the coordinate ring or structure sheaf of a space may contain nilpotent elements. The simplest example is the ring of dual numbersR, where ε2 = 0. This can be motivated by the algebro-geometric point of view on the derivative of a functionf from R to R at a point p. For this, note first that f − fbelongs to the idealIp of functions on R which vanish at p. If the derivative f vanishes at p, then f − f belongs to the square Ip2 of this ideal. Hence the derivative of f at p may be captured by the equivalence class in the quotient spaceIp/Ip2, and the 1-jet of f is the equivalence class of f in the space of all functions modulo Ip2. Algebraic geometers regard this equivalence class as the restriction of f to a thickened version of the point p whose coordinate ring is not R but R which is the quotient space of functions on R modulo Ip2. Such a thickened point is a simple example of a scheme.
Synthetic differential geometry
A third approach to infinitesimals is the method of synthetic differential geometry or smooth infinitesimal analysis. This is closely related to the algebraic-geometric approach, except that the infinitesimals are more implicit and intuitive. The main idea of this approach is to replace the category of sets with another category of smoothly varying sets which is a topos. In this category, one can define the real numbers, smooth functions, and so on, but the real numbers automatically contain nilpotent infinitesimals, so these do not need to be introduced by hand as in the algebraic geometric approach. However the logic in this new category is not identical to the familiar logic of the category of sets: in particular, the law of the excluded middle does not hold. This means that set-theoretic mathematical arguments only extend to smooth infinitesimal analysis if they are constructive. Some regard this disadvantage as a positive thing, since it forces one to find constructive arguments wherever they are available.
Nonstandard analysis
The final approach to infinitesimals again involves extending the real numbers, but in a less drastic way. In the nonstandard analysis approach there are no nilpotent infinitesimals, only invertible ones, which may be viewed as the reciprocals of infinitely large numbers. Such extensions of the real numbers may be constructed explicitly using equivalence classes of sequences of real numbers, so that, for example, the sequence represents an infinitesimal. The first-order logic of this new set of hyperreal numbers is the same as the logic for the usual real numbers, but the completeness axiom does not hold. Nevertheless, this suffices to develop an elementary and quite intuitive approach to calculus using infinitesimals, see transfer principle.