Fair item allocation


Fair item allocation is a kind of a fair division problem in which the items to divide are discrete rather than continuous. The items have to be divided among several partners who value them differently, and each item has to be given as a whole to a single person. This situation arises in various real-life scenarios:
The indivisibility of the items implies that a fair division may not be possible. As an extreme example, if there is only a single item, it must be given to a single partner, but this is not fair to the other partners. This is in contrast to the fair cake-cutting problem, where the dividend is divisible and a fair division always exists. In some cases, the indivisibility problem can be mitigated by introducing monetary payments or time-based rotation, or by discarding some of the items. But such solutions are not always available.
An item assignment problem has several ingredients:
  1. The partners have to express their preferences for the different item-bundles.
  2. The group should decide on a fairness criterion.
  3. Based on the preferences and the fairness criterion, a fair assignment algorithm should be executed to calculate a fair division.
These ingredients are explained in detail below.

Preferences

Combinatorial preferences

A naive way to determine the preferences is asking each partner to supply a numeric value for each possible bundle. For example, if the items to divide are a car and a bicycle, a partner may value the car as 800, the bicycle as 200, and the bundle as 900. There are two problems with this approach:
  1. It may be difficult for a person to calculate exact numeric values to the bundles.
  2. The number of possible bundles can be huge: if there are items then there are possible bundles. For example, if there are 16 items then each partner will have to present his preferences using 65536 numbers.
The first problem motivates the use of ordinal utility rather than cardinal utility. In the ordinal model, each partner should only express a ranking over the different bundles, i.e., say which bundle is the best, which is the second-best, and so on. This may be easier than calculating exact numbers, but it is still difficult if the number of items is large.
The second problem is often handled by working with individual items rather than bundles:
Under suitable assumptions, it is possible to lift the preferences on items to preferences on bundles.
Then, the agents report their valuations/rankings on individual items, and the algorithm calculates for them their valuations/rankings on bundles.

Additive preferences

To make the item-assignment problem simpler, it is common to assume that all items are independent goods.
Then:
The additivity implies that each partner can always choose a "preferable item" from the set of items on the table, and this choice is independent of the other items that the partner may have. This property is used by some fair assignment algorithms that will be described next.

Compact preference representation languages

Compact preference representation languages have been developed as a compromise between the full expressiveness of combinatorial preferences to the simplicity of additive preferences. They provide a succinct representation to some natural classes of utility functions that are more general than additive utilities. Some examples are:

Individual guarantee criteria

An individual guarantee criterion is a criterion that should hold for each individual partner, as long as the partner truthfully reports his preferences. Five such criteria are presented below. They are ordered from the weakest to the strongest :
1. Maximin share: The maximin-share of an agent is the most preferred bundle he could guarantee himself as divider in divide and choose against adversarial opponents. An allocation is called MMS-fair if every agent receives a bundle that he weakly prefers over his MMS.
2. Proportional fair-share : The proportional-fair-share of an agent is 1/n of his utility from the entire set of items. An allocation is called proportional if every agent receives a bundle worth at least his proportional-fair-share.
3. Min-max fair-share : The min-max-fair-share of an agent is the minimal utility that she can hope to get from an allocation if all the other agents have the same preferences as her, when she always receives the best share. It is also the minimal utility that an agent can get for sure in the allocation game “Someone cuts, I choose first”. An allocation is mFS-fair if all agents receive a bundle that they weakly prefer over their mFS. mFS-fairness can be described as the result of the following negotiation process. A certain allocation is suggested. Each agent can object to it by demanding that a different allocation be made by another agent, letting him choose first. Hence, an agent would object to an allocation only if in all partitions, there is a bundle that he strongly prefers over his current bundle. An allocation is mFS-fair iff no agent objects to it, i.e., for every agent there exists a partition in which all bundles are weakly worse than his current share.
For every agent with subadditive utility, the mFS is worth at least. Hence, every mFS-fair allocation is proportional. For every agent with superadditive utility, the MMSis worth at most. Hence, every proportional allocation is MMS-fair. Both inclusions are strict, even when every agent has additive utility. This is illustrated in the following example:
The above implications do not hold when the agents' valuations are not sub/superadditive.
4. Envy-freeness : every agent weakly prefers his own bundle to any other bundle. Every envy-free allocation of all items is mFS-fair; this follows directly from the ordinal definitions and does not depend on additivity. If the valuations are additive, then an EF allocation is also proportional and MMS-fair. Otherwise, an EF allocation may be not proportional and even not MMS. See envy-free item assignment for more details.
5. Competitive equilibrium from Equal Incomes : This criterion is based on the following argument: the allocation process should be considered as a search for an equilibrium between the supply and the demand. A competitive equilibrium is reached when the supply matches the demand. The fairness argument is straightforward: prices and budgets are the same for everyone. CEEI implies EF regardless of additivity. When the agents' preferences are additive and strict, CEEI implies Pareto efficiency.
Several recently suggested fairness criteria are:
6. Envy-freeness-except-1 : For each two agents A and B, if we remove from the bundle of B the item most valuable for A, then A does not envy B. Under monotonicity, an EF1 allocation always exists.
7. Envy-freeness-except-cheapest : For each two agents A and B, if we remove from the bundle of B the item least valuable for A, then A does not envy B. EFx is strictly stronger than EF1. It is not known whether EFx allocations always exist.

Global optimization criteria

A global optimization criterion evaluates a division based on a given social welfare function:
An advantage of global optimization criteria over individual criteria is that welfare-maximizing allocations are Pareto efficient.

Assignment algorithms

Max-min-share fairness

Proportionality

1. Suppose the agents have cardinal utility functions on items. Then, the problem of deciding whether a proportional allocation exists is NP-complete: it can be reduced from the partition problem.
2. Suppose the agents have ordinal rankings on items, with or without indifferences. Then, the problem of deciding whether a necessarily-proportional allocation exists can be solved in polynomial time: it can be reduced to the problem of checking whether a bipartite graph admits a feasible b-matching.
For two agents, a simpler algorithm exists.
3. Suppose the agents have ordinal rankings on items, without indifferences. Then, the problem of deciding whether a necessarily-proportional allocation exists can be solved in polynomial time. It is not known whether the same is true when the agents are allowed to express indifferences.

Min-max-share fairness

The problem of calculating the mFS of an agent is coNP-complete.
The problem of deciding whether an mFS allocation exists is in, but its exact computational complexity is still unknown.

Envy-freeness (without money)

Envy-freeness (with money)

Envy-freeness becomes easier to attain when it is assumed that agents' valuations are quasilinear in money, and thus transferable across agents.
Demange, Gale and Sotomayor showed a natural ascending auction that achieves an envy-free allocation using monetary payments for unit demand bidders.
Fair by Design is a general framework for optimization problems with envy-freeness guarantee that naturally extends fair item assignments using monetary payments.
Cavallo generalizes the traditional binary criteria of envy-freeness, proportionality, and efficiency to measures of degree that range between 0 and 1. In the canonical fair division settings, under any allocatively-efficient mechanism the worst-case welfare rate is 0 and disproportionality rate is 1; in other words, the worst-case results are as bad as possible. This strongly motivates an average-case analysis. He looks for a mechanism that achieves high welfare, low envy, and low disproportionality in expectation across a spectrum of fair division settings. He shows that the VCG mechanism is not a satisfactory candidate, but the redistribution mechanism of
and is.
See also: rental harmony.

Egalitarian-optimal allocations

With general cardinal valuations, finding egalitarian-optimal allocations, or even approximately-optimal allocations, is NP-hard. This can be proved by reduction from the partition problem. When the valuations are more restricted, better approximations are possible:
and
present some stronger hardness results.
The special case of optimizing egalitarian welfare with additive utilities is called "the Santa Claus problem". The problem is still NP-hard and cannot be approximated within a factor > 1/2, but there is an approximation and a more complicated approximation.
See also for a branch-and-bound algorithm for two partners.
The Decreasing Demand procedure returns an egalitarian-optimal division in an ordinal sense: it maximizes the rank, in the linear-ranking of bundles, of the agent with the lowest rank. It works for any number of agents with any ordering of bundles.

Nash-optimal allocations

and prove hardness of calculating utilitarian-optimal and Nash-optimal allocations.
present an approximation procedure for Nash-optimal allocations.

Picking sequences

A picking sequence is a simple protocol where the agents take turns in selecting items, based on some pre-specified sequence of turns. The goal is to design the picking-sequence in a way that maximizes the expected value of a social welfare function under some probabilistic assumptions on the agents' valuations.

Different entitlements

Most research about item assignment assumes that all agents have equal entitlements.
But, in many cases there are agents with different entitlements. One such case is when dividing cabinet ministries among parties in the coalition. It is common to assume that each party should receive ministries according to the number of seats it has in the parliament. See and and for discussions of this problem and some solutions.