Givenness


In linguistics, givenness is a phenomenon in which a speaker assumes that contextual information of a topic of discourse is already known to the listener. The speaker thus considers it unnecessary to supply further contextual information through an expression's , its syntactic form or position, or its patterns of stress and intonation. Givenness involves contextual information in a discourse that is given, or assumed to be known, by the addressee in the moment of utterance. Therefore, a given expression must be known from prior discourse.
Givenness is marked by the absence of emphasis or detailed explanations. For example, when informing a close friend of having taken a long-considered action, an English speaker might simply say, "I did it!" The givenness of the action which "it" refers to results from previously discussing the action. In that utterance, the stress would not fall on "it," but on "did." This example may be contrasted when the nature of the action is new information, such as "I did a cartwheel!" In this case, the object of did— the noun cartwheel— will receive the emphasis.

Definitions

In literature, Prince distinguishes between three different kinds of Givenness:
  1. Givenness: The speaker assumes the hearer can predict or could have predicted a particular linguistic item will or would occur in a particular position within a sentence.
  2. Givenness: The speaker assumes the hearer has or could appropriately have some particular thing/entity/... in his/her CONSCIOUSNESS at the time of hearing the utterance.
  3. Givenness: The speaker assumes the hearer "knows," assumes, or can infer in a particular thing.
Definition by Krifka :
A feature X of an expression α is a Givenness feature if X indicates whether the denotation of α is present in the CG or not, and/or indicates the degree to which it is present in the immediate CG .

Definition by Kratzer and Selkirk :
An expression α is Given in a context C if there is a discourse referent in C that entails α O, C.

Entailment

describes the relation between expression α and expression β when one of the following conditions applies:
Co-reference is one of the two semantic relations that express Givenness. Formally, references α and β both refer to the same entity : α,β ∈ De, α = β. A pronoun ' usually identifies a noun phrase that has been mentioned ' in a prior context and. Examples of:
  1. On my way home, a dog barked at me. I was really frightened by Given.
  2. Did you see Dr. Cramer to get your root canal? - Don't remind me. I'd like to strangle Given.
  3. My neighbor is a funny character. Still, I really like Given.
Alternatively, for non-referential α and β, α is given if the meaning of α and β are extensionally identical or α is a hypernym of β. Formally, α,β ∈ Dt, and α=0 or β=1.
Extensional Identity occurs when an expression α is identical with a prior mentioned expression β, which makes α given.
  1. They brought some beer, but they didn't drink Given ' because it was warm.
A hypernym α of another item β is when the meaning of α includes β as a subcategory, making item α given:
X: I brought
carrots to the picnic.
Y: But I don't like Given
.
However, if instead β includes α, there is hyponymy, and the hyponym
' is considered to be not given:
X: I put some
vegetables in the soup.
Y: Oh I hate
carrots. I hope you didn't put any inside.
Propositional Identity occurs when the proposition ' is given because it is identical with the proposition ' and proposition ' is true.
a. Did you hear that
Otto went to Russia ?
b. I can't believe that
Given .
Asymmetric Entailment occurs when the proposition
' is given because the proposition ' is always true when the proposition ' is true.
a. Did you hear that Otto went to Russia?
b. I can't believe Given.

Expressing givenness

Givenness can be expressed by anaphoric expressions, deletion, or word order.

Anaphoric expressions

expressions indicate the status of their denotations. Anaphoric expressions include personal pronouns, clitics and person inflections, demonstratives, and definite articles as well as indefinite articles that indicate a non-given referent.
a. The crowd approached the gate. The guards were AFRAID of Given.
b. The children were up late. I'm reluctant to WAKE Given.
c. John ate garlic bread. Then Given kissed Mary.

Decantation

Decantation is a form of prosodic reduction.
a. Ten years after John inherited an old farm, he SOLD Given
Here the shed is decanted because it is referring to the prior mentioned farm. Decantation is conditioned by Common Ground Management and can be seen as presuppositional because it expresses a presupposition of a situationally salient antecedent of a particular sort.
Decantation can also occur in indefinite noun phrases:
a. If John paints a hot dog, Sam will eat Given.
Decantation can occur on a focused constituent that is given at the same time, where it does not bear the pitch accent but functions as a focus with only :
a. X: Everyone already knew that Mary only eats VEGETABLES.
Y: If even PAUL knew that Mary only eats Given, then he should have suggested a different RESTAURANT.

Deletion

Deletion is an extreme form of reduction.
a. Bill went to Greenland, and Mary did _ too.
In this example, one can find the deletion of the VP went to Greenland.

Word Order

In the double object construction, given constituents precede new constituents:
a. Bill showed the boy a girl.
*Bill showed a boy the girl.
*Bill showed the girl a boy.

Common Ground

in linguistics refers to shared knowledge between at least two participants in discourse. It is a set of propositions and entities that are known to both speakers, and is updated during the discourse. Common Ground can further be divided into
Two individuals who spend a lot of time together or have many shared experiences can more easily latch onto one another's givenness in their discourse. However, when this phenomenon is relied upon in future or ongoing conversations, deficits in information can begin to develop, and as a result, it becomes difficult to assess givenness in the context of new conversations.