Intersection theory


In mathematics, intersection theory is a branch of algebraic geometry, where subvarieties are intersected on an algebraic variety, and of algebraic topology, where intersections are computed within the cohomology ring. The theory for varieties is older, with roots in Bézout's theorem on curves and elimination theory. On the other hand, the topological theory more quickly reached a definitive form.

Topological intersection form

For a connected oriented manifold of dimension the intersection form is defined on the -th cohomology group by the evaluation of the cup product on the fundamental class in. Stated precisely, there is a bilinear form
given by
with
This is a symmetric form for even, in which case the signature of is defined to be the signature of the form, and an alternating form for odd. These can be referred to uniformly as ε-symmetric forms, where respectively for symmetric and skew-symmetric forms. It is possible in some circumstances to refine this form to an -quadratic form, though this requires additional data such as a framing of the tangent bundle. It is possible to drop the orientability condition and work with coefficients instead.
These forms are important topological invariants. For example, a theorem of Michael Freedman states that simply connected compact 4-manifolds are determined by their intersection forms up to homeomorphism – see intersection form.
By Poincaré duality, it turns out that there is a way to think of this geometrically. If possible, choose representative -dimensional submanifolds, for the Poincaré duals of and. Then is the oriented intersection number of and, which is well-defined because since dimensions of and sum to the total dimension of they generically intersect at isolated points. This explains the terminology intersection form.

Intersection theory in algebraic geometry

in Intersection Theory writes
... if and are subvarieties of a non-singular variety, the intersection product should be an equivalence class of algebraic cycles closely related to the geometry of how, and are situated in. Two extreme cases have been most familiar. If the intersection is proper, i.e., then is a linear combination of the irreducible components of, with coefficients the intersection multiplicities. At the other extreme, if is a non-singular subvariety, the self-intersection formula says that is represented by the top Chern class of the normal bundle of in.

To give a definition, in the general case, of the intersection multiplicity was the major concern of André Weil's 1946 book Foundations of Algebraic Geometry. Work in the 1920s of B. L. van der Waerden had already addressed the question; in the Italian school of algebraic geometry the ideas were well known, but foundational questions were not addressed in the same spirit.

Moving cycles

A well-working machinery of intersecting algebraic cycles and requires more than taking just the set-theoretic intersection of the cycles in question. If the two cycles are in "good position" then the intersection product, denoted, should consist of the set-theoretic intersection of the two subvarieties. However cycles may be in bad position, e.g. two parallel lines in the plane, or a plane containing a line. In both cases the intersection should be a point, because, again, if one cycle is moved, this would be the intersection. The intersection of two cycles and is called proper if the codimension of the intersection is the sum of the codimensions of and, respectively, i.e. the "expected" value.
Therefore, the concept of moving cycles using appropriate equivalence relations on algebraic cycles is used. The equivalence must be broad enough that given any two cycles and, there are equivalent cycles and such that the intersection is proper. Of course, on the other hand, for a second equivalent and, needs to be equivalent to.
For the purposes of intersection theory, rational equivalence is the most important one. Briefly, two -dimensional cycles on a variety are rationally equivalent if there is a rational function on a -dimensional subvariety, i.e. an element of the function field or equivalently a function, such that, where is counted with multiplicities. Rational equivalence accomplishes the needs sketched above.

Intersection multiplicities

The guiding principle in the definition of intersection multiplicities of cycles is continuity in a certain sense. Consider the following elementary example: the intersection of a parabola and an axis should be, because if one of the cycles moves, there are precisely two intersection points which both converge to when the cycles approach the depicted position..
The first fully satisfactory definition of intersection multiplicities was given by Serre: Let the ambient variety be smooth. Further let and be two subvarieties, such that their intersection is proper. The construction is local, therefore the varieties may be represented by two ideals and in the coordinate ring of. Let be an irreducible component of the set-theoretic intersection and its generic point. The multiplicity of in the intersection product is defined by
the alternating sum over the length over the local ring of in of torsion groups of the factor rings corresponding to the subvarieties. This expression is sometimes referred to as Serre's Tor-formula.
Remarks:
The Chow ring is the group of algebraic cycles modulo rational equivalence together with the following commutative intersection product:
whenever V and W meet transversely, where is the decomposition of the set-theoretic intersection into irreducible components.

Self-intersection

Given two subvarieties and, one can take their intersection, but it is also possible, though more subtle, to define the self-intersection of a single subvariety.
Given, for instance, a curve on a surface, its intersection with itself is just itself:. This is clearly correct, but on the other hand unsatisfactory: given any two distinct curves on a surface, they intersect in some set of points, which for instance one can count, obtaining an intersection number, and we may wish to do the same for a given curve: the analogy is that intersecting distinct curves is like multiplying two numbers:, while self-intersection is like squaring a single number:. Formally, the analogy is stated as a symmetric bilinear form and a quadratic form.
A geometric solution to this is to intersect the curve not with itself, but with a slightly pushed off version of itself. In the plane, this just means translating the curve in some direction, but in general one talks about taking a curve that is linearly equivalent to, and counting the intersection, thus obtaining an intersection number, denoted. Note that unlike for distinct curves and, the actual points of intersection are not defined, because they depend on a choice of, but the “self intersection points of can be interpreted as generic points on, where. More properly, the self-intersection point of is the generic point of, taken with multiplicity.
Alternatively, one can “solve” this problem algebraically by dualizing, and looking at the class of – this both gives a number, and raises the question of a geometric interpretation. Note that passing to cohomology classes is analogous to replacing a curve by a linear system.
Note that the self-intersection number can be negative, as the example below illustrates.

Examples

Consider a line in the projective plane : it has self-intersection number 1 since all other lines cross it once: one can push off to, and of, hence. In terms of intersection forms, we say the plane has one of type .
Note that on the affine plane, one might push off to a parallel line, so the number of intersection points depends on the choice of push-off. One says that “the affine plane does not have a good intersection theory”, and intersection theory on non-projective varieties is much more difficult.
A line on a has self-intersection, since a line can be moved off itself. In terms of intersection forms, we say has one of type – there are two basic classes of lines, which intersect each other in one point, but have zero self-intersection.

Blow-ups

A key example of self-intersection numbers is the exceptional curve of a blow-up, which is a central operation in birational geometry.
Given an algebraic surface, blowing up at a point creates a curve. This curve is recognisable by its genus, which is, and its self-intersection number, which is.
Note that as a corollary, and are minimal surfaces, since they do not have any curves with negative self-intersection.
In fact, Castelnuovo’s contraction theorem states the converse: every -curve is the exceptional curve of some blow-up.

Introductory