Lattice (order)
A lattice is an abstract structure studied in the mathematical subdisciplines of order theory and abstract algebra. It consists of a partially ordered set in which every two elements have a unique supremum and a unique infimum. An example is given by the natural numbers, partially ordered by divisibility, for which the unique supremum is the least common multiple and the unique infimum is the greatest common divisor.
Lattices can also be characterized as algebraic structures satisfying certain axiomatic identities. Since the two definitions are equivalent, lattice theory draws on both order theory and universal algebra. Semilattices include lattices, which in turn include Heyting and Boolean algebras. These "lattice-like" structures all admit order-theoretic as well as algebraic descriptions.
Lattices as partially ordered sets
If is a partially ordered set, and is an arbitrary subset, then an element is said to be an upper bound of S if for each. A set may have many upper bounds, or none at all. An upper bound u of S is said to be its least upper bound, or join, or supremum, if for each upper bound x of S. A set need not have a least upper bound, but it cannot have more than one. Dually, is said to be a lower bound of S if for each. A lower bound l of S is said to be its greatest lower bound, or meet, or infimum, if for each lower bound x of S. A set may have many lower bounds, or none at all, but can have at most one greatest lower bound.A partially ordered set is called a join-semilattice if each two-element subset has a join, and is called a meet-semilattice if each two-element subset has a meet, denoted by and respectively. is called a lattice if it is both a join- and a meet-semilattice.
This definition makes ∨ and ∧ binary operations. Both operations are monotone with respect to the given order: and implies that and.
It follows by an induction argument that every non-empty finite subset of a lattice has a least upper bound and a greatest lower bound. With additional assumptions, further conclusions may be possible; see Completeness for more discussion of this subject. That article also discusses how one may rephrase the [|above] definition in terms of the existence of suitable Galois connections between related partially ordered sets—an approach of special interest for the category theoretic approach to lattices, and for formal concept analysis.
A bounded lattice is a lattice that additionally has a greatest element and a least element, which satisfy
Every lattice can be embedded into a bounded lattice by adding an artificial greatest and least element, and every non-empty finite lattice is bounded, by taking the join of all elements, denoted by where.
A partially ordered set is a bounded lattice if and only if every finite set of elements has a join and a meet. For every element x of a poset it is trivially true that
and
, and therefore every element of a poset is both an upper bound and a lower bound of the empty set. This implies that the join of an empty set is the least element, and the meet of the empty set is the greatest element. This is consistent with the associativity and commutativity of meet and join: the join of a union of finite sets is equal to the join of the joins of the sets, and dually, the meet of a union of finite sets is equal to the meet of the meets of the sets, i.e., for finite subsets A and B of a poset L,
and
hold. Taking B to be the empty set,
and
which is consistent with the fact that.
A lattice element y is said to cover another element x, if, but there does not exist a z such that.
Here, means and.
A lattice is called graded, sometimes ranked, if it can be equipped with a rank function r from L to ℕ, sometimes to ℤ, compatible with the ordering such that whenever y covers x, then. The value of the rank function for a lattice element is called its rank.
Given a subset of a lattice,, meet and join restrict to partial functions – they are undefined if their value is not in the subset H. The resulting structure on H is called a . In addition to this extrinsic definition as a subset of some other algebraic structure, a partial lattice can also be intrinsically defined as a set with two partial binary operations satisfying certain axioms.
Lattices as algebraic structures
General lattice
An algebraic structure, consisting of a set L and two binary operations ∨, and ∧, on L is a lattice if the following axiomatic identities hold for all elements a, b, c of L.The following two identities are also usually regarded as axioms, even though they follow from the two absorption laws taken together.
;Idempotent laws
These axioms assert that both and are semilattices. The absorption laws, the only axioms above in which both meet and join appear, distinguish a lattice from an arbitrary pair of semilattice structures and assure that the two semilattices interact appropriately. In particular, each semilattice is the dual of the other.
Bounded lattice
A bounded lattice is an algebraic structure of the form such that is a lattice, 0 is the identity element for the join operation ∨, and 1 is the identity element for the meet operation ∧.;Identity laws
See semilattice for further details.
Connection to other algebraic structures
Lattices have some connections to the family of group-like algebraic structures. Because meet and join both commute and associate, a lattice can be viewed as consisting of two commutative semigroups having the same domain. For a bounded lattice, these semigroups are in fact commutative monoids. The absorption law is the only defining identity that is peculiar to lattice theory.By commutativity and associativity one can think of join and meet as operations on non-empty finite sets, rather than on pairs of elements. In a bounded lattice the join and meet of the empty set can also be defined. This makes bounded lattices somewhat more natural than general lattices, and many authors require all lattices to be bounded.
The algebraic interpretation of lattices plays an essential role in universal algebra.
Connection between the two definitions
An order-theoretic lattice gives rise to the two binary operations ∨ and ∧. Since the commutative, associative and absorption laws can easily be verified for these operations, they make into a lattice in the algebraic sense.The converse is also true. Given an algebraically defined lattice, one can define a partial order ≤ on L by setting
for all elements a and b from L. The laws of absorption ensure that both definitions are equivalent:
a = a ∧ b implies b = b ∨ = ∨ b = a ∨ b
and dually for the other direction.
One can now check that the relation ≤ introduced in this way defines a partial ordering within which binary meets and joins are given through the original operations ∨ and ∧.
Since the two definitions of a lattice are equivalent, one may freely invoke aspects of either definition in any way that suits the purpose at hand.
Examples
- For any set A, the collection of all subsets of A can be ordered via subset inclusion to obtain a lattice bounded by A itself and the empty set. Set intersection and union interpret meet and join, respectively.
- For any set A, the collection of all finite subsets of A, ordered by inclusion, is also a lattice, and will be bounded if and only if A is finite.
- For any set A, the collection of all partitions of A, ordered by refinement, is a lattice.
- The positive integers in their usual order form a lattice, under the operations of "min" and "max". 1 is bottom; there is no top.
- The Cartesian square of the natural numbers, ordered so that if and. The pair is the bottom element; there is no top.
- The natural numbers also form a lattice under the operations of taking the greatest common divisor and least common multiple, with divisibility as the order relation: if a divides b. 1 is bottom; 0 is top. Pic. 2 shows a finite sublattice.
- Every complete lattice is a bounded lattice. This class gives rise to a broad range of practical examples.
- The set of compact elements of an arithmetic complete lattice is a lattice with a least element, where the lattice operations are given by restricting the respective operations of the arithmetic lattice. This is the specific property that distinguishes arithmetic lattices from algebraic lattices, for which the compacts only form a join-semilattice. Both of these classes of complete lattices are studied in domain theory.
Examples of non-lattices
Most partially ordered sets are not lattices, including the following.- A discrete poset, meaning a poset such that implies, is a lattice if and only if it has at most one element. In particular the two-element discrete poset is not a lattice.
- Although the set partially ordered by divisibility is a lattice, the set so ordered is not a lattice because the pair 2, 3 lacks a join; similarly, 2, 3 lacks a meet in
- The set partially ordered by divisibility is not a lattice. Every pair of elements has an upper bound and a lower bound, but the pair 2, 3 has three upper bounds, namely 12, 18, and 36, none of which is the least of those three under divisibility. Likewise the pair 12, 18 has three lower bounds, namely 1, 2, and 3, none of which is the greatest of those three under divisibility.
Morphisms of lattices
Thus f is a homomorphism of the two underlying semilattices. When lattices with more structure are considered, the morphisms should "respect" the extra structure, too. In particular, a bounded-lattice homomorphism f between two bounded lattices L and M should also have the following property:
In the order-theoretic formulation, these conditions just state that a homomorphism of lattices is a function preserving binary meets and joins. For bounded lattices, preservation of least and greatest elements is just preservation of join and meet of the empty set.
Any homomorphism of lattices is necessarily monotone with respect to the associated ordering relation; see Limit preserving function. The converse is not true: monotonicity by no means implies the required preservation of meets and joins, although an order-preserving bijection is a homomorphism if its inverse is also order-preserving.
Given the standard definition of isomorphisms as invertible morphisms, a lattice isomorphism is just a bijective lattice homomorphism. Similarly, a lattice endomorphism is a lattice homomorphism from a lattice to itself, and a lattice automorphism is a bijective lattice endomorphism. Lattices and their homomorphisms form a category.
Sublattices
A sublattice of a lattice L is a subset of L that is a lattice with the same meet and join operations as L. That is, if L is a lattice and M is a subset of L such that for every pair of elements a, b in M both and are in M, then M is a sublattice of L.A sublattice M of a lattice L is a convex sublattice of L, if and x, y in M implies that z belongs to M, for all elements x, y, z in L.
Properties of lattices
We now introduce a number of important properties that lead to interesting special classes of lattices. One, boundedness, has already been discussed.Completeness
A poset is called a complete lattice if all its subsets have both a join and a meet. In particular, every complete lattice is a bounded lattice. While bounded lattice homomorphisms in general preserve only finite joins and meets, complete lattice homomorphisms are required to preserve arbitrary joins and meets.Every poset that is a complete semilattice is also a complete lattice. Related to this result is the interesting phenomenon that there are various competing notions of homomorphism for this class of posets, depending on whether they are seen as complete lattices, complete join-semilattices, complete meet-semilattices, or as join-complete or meet-complete lattices.
Note that "partial lattice" is not the opposite of "complete lattice" – rather, "partial lattice", "lattice", and "complete lattice" are increasingly restrictive definitions.
Conditional completeness
A conditionally complete lattice is a lattice in which every nonempty subset that has an upper bound has a join. Such lattices provide the most direct generalization of the completeness axiom of the real numbers. A conditionally complete lattice is either a complete lattice, or a complete lattice without its maximum element 1, its minimum element 0, or both.Distributivity
Since lattices come with two binary operations, it is natural to ask whether one of them distributes over the other, i.e. whether one or the other of the following dual laws holds for every three elements a, b, c of L:;Distributivity of ∨ over ∧
;Distributivity of ∧ over ∨
A lattice that satisfies the first or, equivalently, the second axiom, is called a distributive lattice.
The only non-distributive lattices with fewer than 6 elements are called M3 and N5; they are shown in Pictures 10 and 11, respectively. A lattice is distributive if and only if it doesn't have a sublattice isomorphic to M3 or N5. Each distributive lattice is isomorphic to a lattice of sets.
For an overview of stronger notions of distributivity that are appropriate for complete lattices and that are used to define more special classes of lattices such as frames and completely distributive lattices, see distributivity in order theory.
Modularity
For some applications the distributivity condition is too strong, and the following weaker property is often useful. A lattice is modular if, for all elements a, b, c of L, the following identity holds.;Modular identity: ∨ = ∧ c.
This condition is equivalent to the following axiom.
;Modular law: implies.
A lattice is modular if and only if it doesn't have a sublattice isomorphic to N5.
Besides distributive lattices, examples of modular lattices are the lattice of two-sided ideals of a ring, the lattice of submodules of a module, and the lattice of normal subgroups of a group. The set of first-order terms with the ordering "is more specific than" is a non-modular lattice used in automated reasoning.
Semimodularity
A finite lattice is modular if and only if it is both upper and lower semimodular. For a graded lattice, semimodularity is equivalent to the following condition on the rank function r:Another equivalent condition is Birkhoff's condition:
A lattice is called lower semimodular if its dual is semimodular. For finite lattices this means that the previous conditions hold with ∨ and ∧ exchanged, "covers" exchanged with "is covered by", and inequalities reversed.
Continuity and algebraicity
In domain theory, it is natural to seek to approximate the elements in a partial order by "much simpler" elements. This leads to the class of continuous posets, consisting of posets where every element can be obtained as the supremum of a directed set of elements that are way-below the element. If one can additionally restrict these to the compact elements of a poset for obtaining these directed sets, then the poset is even algebraic. Both concepts can be applied to lattices as follows:- A continuous lattice is a complete lattice that is continuous as a poset.
- An algebraic lattice is a complete lattice that is algebraic as a poset.
Complements and pseudo-complements
Let L be a bounded lattice with greatest element 1 and least element 0. Two elements x and y of L are complements of each other if and only if:In general, some elements of a bounded lattice might not have a complement, and others might have more than one complement. For example, the set with its usual ordering is a bounded lattice, and ½ does not have a complement. In the bounded lattice N5, the element a has two complements, viz. b and c. A bounded lattice for which every element has a complement is called a complemented lattice.
A complemented lattice that is also distributive is a Boolean algebra. For a distributive lattice, the complement of x, when it exists, is unique.
In the case the complement is unique, we write and equivalently,. The corresponding unary operation over L, called complementation, introduces an analogue of logical negation into lattice theory.
Heyting algebras are an example of distributive lattices where some members might be lacking complements. Every element x of a Heyting algebra has, on the other hand, a pseudo-complement, also denoted ¬x. The pseudo-complement is the greatest element y such that. If the pseudo-complement of every element of a Heyting algebra is in fact a complement, then the Heyting algebra is in fact a Boolean algebra.
Jordan–Dedekind chain condition
A chain from x0 to xn is a set, where.The length of this chain is n, or one less than its number of elements. A chain is maximal if xi covers xi−1
for all.
If for any pair, x and y, where, all maximal chains from x to y have the same length, then the lattice is said to satisfy the Jordan–Dedekind chain condition.
Free lattices
Any set X may be used to generate the free semilattice FX. The free semilattice is defined to consist of all of the finite subsets of X, with the semilattice operation given by ordinary set union. The free semilattice has the universal property. For the free lattice over a set X, Whitman gave a construction based on polynomials over Xs members.Important lattice-theoretic notions
We now define some order-theoretic notions of importance to lattice theory. In the following, let x be an element of some lattice L. If L has a bottom element 0, is sometimes required. x is called:- Join irreducible if implies or for all a, b in L. When the first condition is generalized to arbitrary joins, x is called completely join irreducible. The dual notion is meet irreducibility. For example, in Pic. 2, the elements 2, 3, 4, and 5 are join irreducible, while 12, 15, 20, and 30 are meet irreducible. In the lattice of real numbers with the usual order, each element is join irreducible, but none is completely join irreducible.
- Join prime if implies or. This too can be generalized to obtain the notion completely join prime. The dual notion is meet prime. Every join-prime element is also join irreducible, and every meet-prime element is also meet irreducible. The converse holds if L is distributive.
- Atomic if for every nonzero element x of L, there exists an atom a of L such that ;
- Atomistic if every element of L is a supremum of atoms.
Applications that use lattice theory
Note that in many applications the sets are only partial lattices: not every pair of elements has a meet or join.- Pointless topology
- Lattice of subgroups
- Spectral space
- Invariant subspace
- Closure operator
- Abstract interpretation
- Subsumption lattice
- Fuzzy set theory
- Algebraizations of first-order logic
- Semantics of programming languages
- Domain theory
- Ontology
- Multiple inheritance
- Formal concept analysis and lattice miner
- Bloom filter
- Information flow
- Ordinal optimization
- Quantum logic
- Median graph
- Knowledge space
- Regular language learning
- Analogical modeling