The method of exhaustion is a method of finding the area of a shape by inscribing inside it a sequence of polygons whose areas converge to the area of the containing shape. If the sequence is correctly constructed, the difference in area between the nth polygon and the containing shape will become arbitrarily small as n becomes large. As this difference becomes arbitrarily small, the possible values for the area of the shape are systematically "exhausted" by the lower bound areas successively established by the sequence members. The method of exhaustion typically required a form of proof by contradiction, known as reductio ad absurdum. This amounts to finding an area of a region by first comparing it to the area of a second region. The proof involves assuming that the true area is greater than the second area, and then proving that assertion false, and then assuming that it is less than the second area, and proving that assertion false, too.
History
The idea originated in the late 5th century BC with Antiphon, although it is not entirely clear how well he understood it. The theory was made rigorous a few decades later by Eudoxus of Cnidus, who used it to calculate areas and volumes. It was later reinvented in China by Liu Hui in the 3rd century AD in order to find the area of a circle. The first use of the term was in 1647 by Gregory of Saint Vincent in Opus geometricum quadraturae circuli et sectionum. The method of exhaustion is seen as a precursor to the methods of calculus. The development of analytical geometry and rigorous integral calculus in the 17th-19th centuries subsumed the method of exhaustion so that it is no longer explicitly used to solve problems. An important alternative approach was Cavalieri's principle, also termed the method of indivisibles which eventually evolved into the infinitesimal calculus of Roberval, Torricelli, Wallis, Leibniz, and others.
Euclid
used the method of exhaustion to prove the following six propositions in the 12th book of his Elements. Proposition 2: The area of circles is proportional to the square of their diameters. Proposition 5: The volumes of two tetrahedra of the same height are proportional to the areas of their triangular bases. Proposition 10: The volume of a cone is a third of the volume of the corresponding cylinder which has the same base and height. Proposition 11: The volume of a cone of the same height is proportional to the area of the base. Proposition 12: The volume of a cone that is similar to another is proportional to the cube of the ratio of the diameters of the bases. Proposition 18: The volume of a sphere is proportional to the cube of its diameter.
Archimedes
used the method of exhaustion as a way to compute the area inside a circle by filling the circle with a polygon of a greater area and greater number of sides. The quotient formed by the area of this polygon divided by the square of the circle radius can be made arbitrarily close to π as the number of polygon sides becomes large, proving that the area inside the circle of radius r is πr2, π being defined as the ratio of the circumference to the diameter or of the area of the circle to the square of its radius. He also provided the bounds 3 + 10/71 < π < 3 + 10/70, by comparing the perimeters of the circle with the perimeters of the inscribed and circumscribed 96-sided regular polygons. Other results he obtained with the method of exhaustion included
The area bounded by the intersection of a line and a parabola is 4/3 that of the triangle having the same base and height;