Motive (algebraic geometry)


In algebraic geometry, motives is a theory proposed by Alexander Grothendieck in the 1960s to unify the vast array of similarly behaved cohomology theories such as singular cohomology, de Rham cohomology, etale cohomology, and crystalline cohomology. Philosophically, a 'motif' is the 'cohomology essence' of a variety.
In the formulation of Grothendieck for smooth projective varieties, a motive is a triple, where X is a smooth projective variety, is an idempotent correspondence, and m an integer, however, such a triple contains almost no information outside the context of Grothendieck's category of pure motives, where a morphism from to is given by a correspondence of degree. A more object focussed approach is taken by Pierre Deligne in Le Groupe Fondamental de la Droite Projective Moins Trois Points. In that article, a motive is a 'system of realisations'. That is, a tuple
consisting of modules
over the rings
respectively, various comparison isomorphisms
between the obvious base changes of these modules, filtrations, a -action on and a "Frobenius" automorphism of. This data is modeled on the cohomologies of a smooth projective -variety and the structures and compatibilities they admit, and gives an idea about what kind of information is contained a motive.

Introduction

The theory of motives was originally conjectured as an attempt to unify a rapidly multiplying array of cohomology theories, including Betti cohomology, de Rham cohomology, l-adic cohomology, and crystalline cohomology. The general hope is that equations like
can be put on increasingly solid mathematical footing with a deep meaning. Of course, the above equations are already known to be true in many senses, such as in the sense of CW-complex where "+" corresponds to attaching cells, and in the sense of various cohomology theories, where "+" corresponds to the direct sum.
From another viewpoint, motives continue the sequence of generalizations from rational functions on varieties to divisors on varieties to Chow groups of varieties. The generalization happens in more than one direction, since motives can be considered with respect to more types of equivalence than rational equivalence. The admissible equivalences are given by the definition of an adequate equivalence relation.

Definition of pure motives

The category of pure motives often proceeds in three steps. Below we describe the case of Chow motives, where k is any field.

First step: category of (degree 0) correspondences, \operatorname{Corr}(k)

The objects of are simply smooth projective varieties over k. The morphisms are correspondences. They generalize morphisms of varieties, which can be associated with their graphs in, to fixed dimensional Chow cycles on.
It will be useful to describe correspondences of arbitrary degree, although morphisms in are correspondences of degree 0. In detail, let X and Y be smooth projective varieties and consider a decomposition of X into connected components:
If, then the correspondences of degree r from X to Y are
where denotes the Chow-cycles of codimension k. Correspondences are often denoted using the "⊢"-notation, e.g.,. For any and their composition is defined by
where the dot denotes the product in the Chow ring.
Returning to constructing the category notice that the composition of degree 0 correspondences is degree 0. Hence we define morphisms of to be degree 0 correspondences.
The following association is a functor :
Just like the category has direct sums and tensor products. It is a preadditive category. The sum of morphisms is defined by

Second step: category of pure effective Chow motives, \operatorname{Chow}^{\operatorname{eff}}(k)

The transition to motives is made by taking the pseudo-abelian envelope of :
In other words, effective Chow motives are pairs of smooth projective varieties X and idempotent correspondences α: XX, and morphisms are of a certain type of correspondence:
Composition is the above defined composition of correspondences, and the identity morphism of is defined to be α : XX.
The association,
where ΔX := denotes the diagonal of X × X, is a functor. The motive is often called the motive associated to the variety X.
As intended, Choweff is a pseudo-abelian category. The direct sum of effective motives is given by
The tensor product of effective motives is defined by
where
The tensor product of morphisms may also be defined. Let f1 : → and f2 : → be morphisms of motives. Then let γ1A and γ2A be representatives of f1 and f2. Then
where πi : X1 × X2 × Y1 × Y2Xi × Yi are the projections.

Third step: category of pure Chow motives, Chow(''k'')

To proceed to motives, we adjoin to Choweff a formal inverse of a motive called the Lefschetz motive. The effect is that motives become triples instead of pairs. The Lefschetz motive L is
If we define the motive 1, called the trivial Tate motive, by 1 := h, then the elegant equation
holds, since
The tensor inverse of the Lefschetz motive is known as the Tate motive, T := L−1. Then we define the category of pure Chow motives by
A motive is then a triple
such that morphisms are given by correspondences
and the composition of morphisms comes from composition of correspondences.
As intended, is a rigid pseudo-abelian category.

Other types of motives

In order to define an intersection product, cycles must be "movable" so we can intersect them in general position. Choosing a suitable equivalence relation on cycles will guarantee that every pair of cycles has an equivalent pair in general position that we can intersect. The Chow groups are defined using rational equivalence, but other equivalences are possible, and each defines a different sort of motive. Examples of equivalences, from strongest to weakest, are
The literature occasionally calls every type of pure motive a Chow motive, in which case a motive with respect to algebraic equivalence would be called a Chow motive modulo algebraic equivalence.

Mixed motives

For a fixed base field k, the category of mixed motives is a conjectural abelian tensor category, together with a contravariant functor
taking values on all varieties. This should be such that motivic cohomology defined by
coincides with the one predicted by algebraic K-theory, and contains the category of Chow motives in a suitable sense. The existence of such a category was conjectured by Alexander Beilinson.
Instead of constructing such a category, it was proposed by Deligne to first construct a category DM having the properties one expects for the derived category
Getting MM back from DM would then be accomplished by a motivic t-structure.
The current state of the theory is that we do have a suitable category DM. Already this category is useful in applications. Vladimir Voevodsky's Fields Medal-winning proof of the Milnor conjecture uses these motives as a key ingredient.
There are different definitions due to Hanamura, Levine and Voevodsky. They are known to be equivalent in most cases and we will give Voevodsky's definition below. The category contains Chow motives as a full subcategory and gives the "right" motivic cohomology. However, Voevodsky also shows that it does not admit a motivic t-structure.

Geometric Mixed Motives

Notation

Here we will fix a field of characteristic and let be our coefficient ring. Set as the category of quasi-projective varieties over are separated schemes of finite type. We will also let be the subcategory of smooth varieties.

Smooth varieties with correspondences

Given a smooth variety and a variety call an integral closed subscheme which is finite over and surjective over a component of a prime correspondence from to. Then, we can take the set of prime correspondences from to and construct a free -module. Its elements are called finite correspondences. Then, we can form an additive category whose objects are smooth varieties and morphisms are given by smooth correspondences. The only non-trivial part of this "definition" is the fact that we need to describe compositions. These are given by a push-pull formula from the theory of Chow rings.
Examples
Typical examples of prime correspondences come from the graph of a morphism of varieties.

Localizing the homotopy category

From here we can form the homotopy category of bounded complexes of smooth correspondences. Here smooth varieties will be denoted. If we localize this category with respect to the smallest thick subcategory containing morphisms
and
then we can form the triangulated category of effective geometric motives Note that the first class of morphisms are localizing -homotopies of varieties while the second will give the category of geometric mixed motives the Mayer–Vietoris sequence.
Also, note that this category has a tensor structure given by the product of varieties, so.

Inverting the Tate motive

Using the triangulated structure we can construct a triangle
from the canonical map. We will set and call it the Tate motive. Taking the iterative tensor product lets us construct. If we have an effective geometric motive we let denote Moreover, this behaves functorially and forms a triangulated functor. Finally, we can define the category of geometric mixed motives as the category of pairs for an effective geometric mixed motive and an integer representing the twist by the Tate motive. The hom-groups are then the colimit

Explanation for non-specialists

A commonly applied technique in mathematics is to study objects carrying a particular structure by introducing a category whose morphisms preserve this structure. Then one may ask, when are two given objects isomorphic and ask for a "particularly nice" representative in each isomorphism class. The classification of algebraic varieties, i.e. application of this idea in the case of algebraic varieties, is very difficult due to the highly non-linear structure of the objects. The relaxed question of studying varieties up to birational isomorphism has led to the field of birational geometry. Another way to handle the question is to attach to a given variety X an object of more linear nature, i.e. an object amenable to the techniques of linear algebra, for example a vector space. This "linearization" goes usually under the name of cohomology.
There are several important cohomology theories, which reflect different structural aspects of varieties. The theory of motives is an attempt to find a universal way to linearize algebraic varieties, i.e. motives are supposed to provide a cohomology theory that embodies all these particular cohomologies. For example, the genus of a smooth projective curve C which is an interesting invariant of the curve, is an integer, which can be read off the dimension of the first Betti cohomology group of C. So, the motive of the curve should contain the genus information. Of course, the genus is a rather coarse invariant, so the motive of C is more than just this number.

The search for a universal cohomology

Each algebraic variety X has a corresponding motive , so the simplest examples of motives are:
These 'equations' hold in many situations, namely for de Rham cohomology and Betti cohomology, l-adic cohomology, the number of points over any finite field, and in multiplicative notation for local zeta-functions.
The general idea is that one motive has the same structure in any reasonable cohomology theory with good formal properties; in particular, any Weil cohomology theory will have such properties. There are different Weil cohomology theories, they apply in different situations and have values in different categories, and reflect different structural aspects of the variety in question:
All these cohomology theories share common properties, e.g. existence of Mayer-Vietoris sequences, homotopy invariance the product of X with the affine line) and others. Moreover, they are linked by comparison isomorphisms, for example Betti cohomology of a smooth variety X over with finite coefficients is isomorphic to l-adic cohomology with finite coefficients.
The theory of motives is an attempt to find a universal theory which embodies all these particular cohomologies and their structures and provides a framework for "equations" like
In particular, calculating the motive of any variety X directly gives all the information about the several Weil cohomology theories HBetti, HDR etc.
Beginning with Grothendieck, people have tried to precisely define this theory for many years.

Motivic cohomology

Motivic cohomology itself had been invented before the creation of mixed motives by means of algebraic K-theory. The above category provides a neat way to define it by
where n and m are integers and is the m-th tensor power of the Tate object which in Voevodsky's setting is the complex shifted by –2, and means the usual shift in the triangulated category.

Conjectures related to motives

The standard conjectures were first formulated in terms of the interplay of algebraic cycles and Weil cohomology theories. The category of pure motives provides a categorical framework for these conjectures.
The standard conjectures are commonly considered to be very hard and are open in the general case. Grothendieck, with Bombieri, showed the depth of the motivic approach by producing a conditional proof of the Weil conjectures, assuming the standard conjectures to hold.
For example, the Künneth standard conjecture, which states the existence of algebraic cycles πiX × X inducing the canonical projectors HHiH implies that every pure motive M decomposes in graded pieces of weight n: M = ⊕GrnM. The terminology weights comes from a similar decomposition of, say, de-Rham cohomology of smooth projective varieties, see Hodge theory.
Conjecture D, stating the concordance of numerical and homological equivalence, implies the equivalence of pure motives with respect to homological and numerical equivalence.. Jannsen proved the following unconditional result: the category of motives over a field is abelian and semisimple if and only if the chosen equivalence relation is numerical equivalence.
The Hodge conjecture, may be neatly reformulated using motives: it holds iff the Hodge realization mapping any pure motive with rational coefficients to its Hodge structure is a full functor . Here pure motive means pure motive with respect to homological equivalence.
Similarly, the Tate conjecture is equivalent to: the so-called Tate realization, i.e. ℓ-adic cohomology, is a full functor , which takes values in semi-simple representations..

Tannakian formalism and motivic Galois group

To motivate the motivic Galois group, fix a field k and consider the functor
which maps K to the set of embeddings of K into an algebraic closure of k. In Galois theory this functor is shown to be an equivalence of categories. Notice that fields are 0-dimensional. Motives of this kind are called Artin motives. By -linearizing the above objects, another way of expressing the above is to say that Artin motives are equivalent to finite -vector spaces together with an action of the Galois group.
The objective of the motivic Galois group is to extend the above equivalence to higher-dimensional varieties. In order to do this, the technical machinery of Tannakian category theory is used. Its purpose is to shed light on both the Hodge conjecture and the Tate conjecture, the outstanding questions in algebraic cycle theory. Fix a Weil cohomology theory H. It gives a functor from Mnum to finite-dimensional -vector spaces. It can be shown that the former category is a Tannakian category. Assuming the equivalence of homological and numerical equivalence, i.e. the above standard conjecture D, the functor H is an exact faithful tensor-functor. Applying the Tannakian formalism, one concludes that Mnum is equivalent to the category of representations of an algebraic group G, known as the motivic Galois group.

The motivic Galois group is to the theory of motives what the Mumford–Tate group is to Hodge theory. Again speaking in rough terms, the Hodge and Tate conjectures are types of invariant theory. The motivic Galois group has the surrounding representation theory.

Survey Articles

*