Mutual majority criterion


The mutual majority criterion is a criterion used to compare voting systems. It is also known as the majority criterion for solid coalitions and the generalized majority criterion. The criterion states that if there is a subset S of the candidates, such that more than half of the voters strictly prefer every member of S to every candidate outside of S, this majority voting sincerely, the winner must come from S. This is similar to but stricter than the majority criterion, where the requirement applies only to the case that S contains a single candidate. The mutual majority criterion is the single-winner case of the Droop proportionality criterion.
The Schulze method, ranked pairs, instant-runoff voting, Nanson's method, and Bucklin voting pass this criterion. All Smith-efficient Condorcet methods pass the mutual majority criterion.
The plurality vote, approval voting, range voting, the Borda count, and minimax fail this criterion.
Methods which pass mutual majority but fail the Condorcet criterion can nullify the voting power of voters outside the mutual majority. Instant runoff voting is notable for excluding up to half of voters by this combination.
Methods which pass the majority criterion but fail mutual majority can have a spoiler effect, since if a non-mutual majority-preferred candidates wins instead of a mutual majority-preferred candidate, then if all but one of the candidates in the mutual majority-preferred set drop out, the remaining mutual majority-preferred candidate will win, which is an improvement from the perspective of all voters in the majority.

Examples

Borda count

The mutual majority criterion implies the majority criterion so the Borda count's failure of the latter is also a failure of the mutual majority criterion. The set solely containing candidate A is a set S as described in the definition.

Minimax

Assume four candidates A, B, C, and D with 100 voters and the following preferences:
19 voters17 voters17 voters16 voters16 voters15 voters
1. C1. D1. B1. D1. A1. D
2. A2. C2. C2. B2. B2. A
3. B3. A3. A3. C3. C3. B
4. D4. B4. D4. A4. D4. C

The results would be tabulated as follows:
Result: Candidates A, B and C each are strictly preferred by more than the half of the voters over D, so is a set S as described in the definition and D is a Condorcet loser. Nevertheless, Minimax declares D the winner because its biggest defeat is significantly the smallest compared to the defeats A, B and C caused each other.

Plurality

Assume the Tennessee capital election example.
42% of voters
26% of voters
15% of voters
17% of voters

  1. Memphis
  2. Nashville
  3. Chattanooga
  4. Knoxville
  • Nashville
  • Chattanooga
  • Knoxville
  • Memphis
  • Chattanooga
  • Knoxville
  • Nashville
  • Memphis
  • Knoxville
  • Chattanooga
  • Nashville
  • Memphis
  • There are 58% of the voters who prefer Nashville, Chattanooga and Knoxville over Memphis, so the three cities build a set S as described in the definition. But since the supporters of the three cities split their votes, Memphis wins under Plurality.

    Range voting

    Range voting does not satisfy the Majority criterion. The set solely containing candidate A is a set S as described in the definition, but B is the winner. Thus, range voting does not satisfy the mutual majority criterion.