Naturalness (physics)
In physics, naturalness is the property that the dimensionless ratios between free parameters or physical constants appearing in a physical theory should take values "of order 1" and that free parameters are not fine-tuned. That is, a natural theory would have parameter ratios with values like 2.34 rather than 234000 or 0.000234.
The requirement that satisfactory theories should be "natural" in this sense is a current of thought initiated around the 1960s in particle physics. It is an aesthetic criterion, not a physical one, that arises from the seeming non-naturalness of the standard model and the broader topics of the hierarchy problem, fine-tuning, and the anthropic principle. However it does tend to suggest a possible area of weakness or future development for current theories such as the Standard Model, where some parameters vary by many orders of magnitude, and which require extensive "fine-tuning" of their current values of the models concerned. The concern is that it is not yet clear whether these seemingly exact values we currently recognize, have arisen by chance or whether they arise from a more advanced theory not yet developed, in which these turn out to be expected and well-explained, because of other factors not yet part of particle physics models.
The concept of naturalness is not always compatible with Occam's razor, since many instances of "natural" theories have more parameters than "fine-tuned" theories such as the Standard Model. Naturalness in physics is closely related to the issue of fine-tuning, and over the past decade many scientists argued that the principle of naturalness is a specific application of Bayesian statistics.
Overview
A simple example:Suppose a physics model requires four parameters which allow it to produce a very high quality working model, calculations, and predictions of some aspect of our physical universe. Suppose we find through experiments that the parameters have values:
- 1.2
- 1.31
- 0.9 and
- 404,331,557,902,116,024,553,602,703,216.58.
One answer given by some physicists is the anthropic principle. If the universe came to exist by chance, and perhaps vast numbers of other universes exist or have existed, then life capable of physics experiments only arose in universes that by chance had very balanced forces. All the universes where the forces were not balanced, didn't develop life capable of the question. So if a lifeform like human beings asks such a question, it must have arisen in a universe having balanced forces, however rare that might be. So when we look, that is what we would expect to find, and what we do find.
A second answer is that perhaps there is a deeper understanding of physics, which, if we discovered and understood it, would make clear these aren't really fundamental parameters and there is a good reason why they have the exact values we have found, because they all derive from other more fundamental parameters that are not so unbalanced.
Introduction
In particle physics, the assumption of naturalness means that, unless a more detailed explanation exists, all conceivable terms in the effective action that preserve the required symmetries should appear in this effective action with natural coefficients.In an effective field theory, is the cutoff scale, an energy or length scale at which the theory breaks down. Due to dimensional analysis, natural coefficients have the form
where is the dimension of the field operator; and is a dimensionless number which should be "random" and smaller than 1 at the scale where the effective theory breaks down. Further renormalization group running can reduce the value of at an energy scale, but by a small factor proportional to.
Some parameters in the effective action of the Standard Model seem to have far smaller coefficients than required by consistency with the assumption of naturalness, leading to some of the fundamental open questions in physics. In particular:
- The naturalness of the QCD "theta parameter" leads to the strong CP problem, because it is very small rather than of order of magnitude unity.
- The naturalness of the Higgs mass leads to the hierarchy problem, because it is 17 orders of magnitude smaller than the Planck mass that characterizes gravity.
- The naturalness of the cosmological constant leads to the cosmological constant problem because it is at least 40 and perhaps as much as 100 or more orders of magnitude smaller than naively expected.
In models with large extra dimensions, the assumption of naturalness is violated for operators which multiply field operators that create objects which are localized at different positions in the extra dimensions.
Naturalness and the gauge hierarchy problem
A more practical definition of naturalness is that for any observable which consists of independent contributionsthen all *independent* contributions to should be comparable to or less than.
Otherwise, if one contribution, say, then some other independent contribution would have to be fine-tuned to a large opposite-sign value
such as to maintain at its measured value. Such fine-tuning is regarded as unnatural and indicative of some missing ingredient in the theory.
For instance, in the Standard Model with Higgs potential given by
the physical Higgs boson mass is calculated to be
where the quadratically divergent radiative correction is given by
where is the top-quark Yukawa coupling, is the SU gauge coupling and
is the energy cut-off to the divergent loop integrals. As
increases, then can be freely dialed so as
to maintain at its measured value.
By insisting on naturalness, then.
Solving for, one finds
TeV.
This then implies that the Standard Model as a natural effective field theory is only valid up to the 1 TeV energy scale.
Sometimes it is complained that this argument depends on the regularization scheme introducing the cut-off
and perhaps the problem disappears under dimensional regularization.
In this case, if new particles which couple to the Higgs are introduced, one once again regains the quadratic divergence now in terms of the new particle squared masses.
For instance, if one includes see-saw neutrinos into the Standard Model, then would blow up to near the see-saw scale, typically expected in the GeV range.
Naturalness, supersymmetry and the little hierarchy
By supersymmetrizing the Standard Model, one arrives at a solution to thegauge hierarchy, or big hierarchy, problem in that supersymmetry guarantees
cancellation of quadratic divergences to all orders in perturbation theory.
The simplest supersymmetrization of the SM leads to the
Minimal Supersymmetric Standard Model or MSSM.
In the MSSM, each SM particle has a partner particle known as a super-partner or
sparticle. For instance, the left- and right-electron helicity components
have scalar partner selectrons and
respectively whilst the eight colored gluons have eight colored spin-1/2 gluino
superpartners. The MSSM Higgs sector must necessarily be expanded to include two
rather than one doublets leading to five physical Higgs particles
and whilst three of the eight
Higgs component fields are absorbed by the and
bosons to make them massive.
The MSSM is actually
supported by three different sets of measurements which test for the presence of
virtual superpartners: 1. the celebrated weak scale measurements of
the three gauge couplings strengths are just what is needed for gauge coupling
unification at a scale GeV, 2. the value of
GeV falls squarely in the range needed to trigger a radiatively-driven
breakdown in electroweak symmetry and
3. the measured value of
GeV falls within the narrow window of allowed values for the MSSM.
Nonetheless, verification of weak scale SUSY requires
the direct observation of at least some of the superpartners at
sufficiently energetic colliding beam experiments.
As recent as 2017, the CERN Large Hadron Collider, a collider operating at center-of-mass energy 13 TeV,
has not found any evidence for superpartners. This has led to mass limits on the
gluino TeV and on the lighter top squark
TeV.
Along with these limits, the rather large measured value of GeV
seems to require TeV-scale highly mixed top squarks.
These combined measurements have raised concern now about an emerging Little Hierarchy
problem characterized by.
Under the Little Hierarchy, one might expect the now log-divergent light Higgs mass to
blow up to the sparticle mass scale unless one fine-tunes. The Little Hierarchy
problem has led to concern that WSS is perhaps not realized in nature, or at least not
in the manner typically expected by theorists in years past.
Status of naturalness and the little hierarchy
In the MSSM, the light Higgs mass is calculated to bewhere the mixing and loop contributions are but where in most
models, the soft SUSY breaking up-Higgs mass is driven to large,
TeV-scale negative values. Then, to maintain
the measured value of GeV, one must tune the superpotential
mass term to some large positive value.
Alternatively, for natural SUSY, one may expect that runs to small negative values
in which case both and are of order 100-200 GeV.
This already leads to a prediction: since is supersymmetric and feeds mass to both SM particles
and superpartners, then it is expected
from the natural MSSM that light higgsinos exist nearby to the 100-200 GeV scale.
This simple realization has profound implications for WSS collider
and dark matter searches.
Naturalness in the MSSM has historically been expressed in terms of the
boson mass, and indeed this approach leads to more stringent upper bounds
on sparticle masses. By minimizing the scalar potential of the
MSSM, then one may relate the measured value of GeV to the
SUSY Lagrangian parameters:
Here, is the ratio of Higgs field vacuum expectation
values and is the down-Higgs soft breaking
mass term. The and contain
a variety of loop corrections labelled by indices i and j, the most important of
which typically comes from the top-squarks.
In the renowned review work of P. Nilles, titled "Supersymmetry, Supergravity and Particle Physics", published on Phys.Rept. 110 1-162, one finds the sentence "Experiments within the next five to ten years will enable us to decide whether supersymmetry as a solution of the naturalness problem of the weak interaction scale is a myth or a reality".