Open theism
Open theism, also known as openness theology and free will theism, is a theological movement that has developed within Christianity as a rejection to the synthesis of Greek philosophy and Christian theology. Open theism is typically advanced as a biblically motivated and philosophically consistent theology of human and divine freedom, with an emphasis on what this means for the content of God's foreknowledge and exercise of God's power.
Noted Open Theist theologian Thomas J. Oord identifies four paths to open and relational theology:
- following the biblical witness,
- following themes in some Christian theological traditions,
- following the philosophy of free will, and
- following the path of reconciling faith and science.
Exposition of open theism
In short, open theism says that since God and humans are free, God's knowledge is dynamic and God's providence flexible. While several versions of traditional theism picture God's knowledge of the future as a singular, fixed trajectory, open theism sees it as a plurality of branching possibilities, with some possibilities becoming settled as time moves forward. Thus, the future as well as God's knowledge of it is open. Other versions of classical theism hold that God fully determines the future, entailing that there is no free choice. Yet other versions of classical theism hold that even though there is freedom of choice, God's omniscience necessitates God foreknowing what free choices are made. Open theists hold that these versions of classical theism do not agree with:- the biblical concept of God
- the biblical understanding of divine and creaturely freedom
Comparison of open and Reformed theism
The following chart compares beliefs about key doctrines as stated by open theists and Calvinists after "the period of controversy" between adherents of the two theisms began in 1994. During this period the "theology of open theism… rocked the evangelical world".Doctrine | Open Theism | Calvinism |
Scripture . "In the Christian tradition, the Old and the New Testaments are considered Holy Scripture in that they are, or convey, the self-revelation of God." | "Committed to affirming the infallibility of Scripture" | Scripture is "the infallible Word of God". |
God's Power. "God's power is limited only by God's own nature and not by any external force." | "God is all-powerful." | "God is all-powerful." |
God's Sovereignty. "God's ultimate Lordship and rule over the universe". | Portraying God as ordaining whatever happens reduces "humans to robots". | "Nothing that exists or occurs falls outside God's ordaining will. Nothing, including no evil person or thing or event or deed." |
God's Perfection. "God as lacking nothing and free of all moral imperfection". | Believes in " the absolute perfection of God." | Believes that, because "Scripture says" it, God "will always do what is right". |
God's Foreknowledge. "God's knowing things and events before they happen in history". | "God is omniscient" about "settled" reality, but the future that God "leaves open" can be known only as open "possibility" without specific foreknowledge. | Classically Augustinian-Calvinist view: "God knows the future because he preordains it." |
The Fall. "The disobedience and sin of Adam and Eve that caused them to lose the state of innocence in which they had been created. This event plunged them and all mankind into a state of sin and corruption." | God "does not unilaterally and irrevocably decide what to do". God's decisions are influenced by "human attitudes and responses". | "Ultimate reason" for the Fall was "God's ordaining will". |
Free Will. "The term seeks to describe the free choice of the will which all persons possess. Theological debates have arisen over the ways and to the extent to which sin has affected the power to choose good over evil, and hence one's 'free will'." | Promotes incompatibilism, the doctrine that "the agent's power to do otherwise" is "a necessary condition for acting freely". | Promotes compatibilism, the doctrine that "freedom" of the will requires only "the power or ability to do what one will to do" without constraint or impediment, even if what one wills is determined. |
Free Will and God's Sovereignty. A "caustic debate" began about 1990 over "God's sovereignty and human free will". | Saying that God governs human choices reduces "angels or humans to robots in order to attain his objectives." | God governs "the choices of human beings", but without "cancelling freedom and responsibility". |
Theodicy issue. "The justification of a deity's justice and goodness in light of suffering and evil". | To meet the "conditions of love", God exercises "general rather than specific sovereignty, which explains why God does not prevent all evil". Also, God "does not completely control or in any sense will evil" because the world is "held hostage to a cosmic evil force". | Because "Scripture says" it, God "will always do what is right". |
Historical development
Open theists have named open theism precursors to document their assertion that "the open view of the future is not a recent concept," but has a long history.The first known post-biblical Christian writings advocating concepts similar to open theism with regard to the issue of foreknowledge are found in the writings of Calcidius, a 4th-century interpreter of Plato. It was affirmed in the 16th century by Socinus, and in the early 18th century by Samuel Fancourt and by Andrew Ramsay. In the 19th century several theologians wrote in defense of this idea, including Isaak August Dorner, Gustav Fechner, Otto Pfleiderer, Jules Lequier, Adam Clarke, Billy Hibbard, Joel Hayes, T.W. Brents, and Lorenzo D. McCabe. Contributions to this defense increased as the century drew to a close.
The dynamic omniscience view has been affirmed by a number of non Christians as well: Cicero Alexander of Aphrodisias and Porphyry. God's statement to Abraham “Now I know that you fear me” was much discussed by Medieval Jewish theologians. Two significant Jewish thinkers who affirmed dynamic omniscience as the proper interpretation of the passage were Ibn Ezra and Gersonides.
Sergei Bulgakov, an early-20th-century Russian Orthodox priest and theologian advocated the use of the term panentheism, which articulated a necessary link between God and creation as consequence of God's free love and not as a natural necessity. His sophiology has sometimes been seen as a precursor to 'open theism'.
Millard Erickson belittles such precursors to open theism as "virtually unknown or unnoticed."
After 1980
The term "open theism" was introduced in 1980 with theologian Richard Rice's book The Openness of God: The Relationship of Divine Foreknowledge and Human Free Will. The broader articulation of open theism was given in 1994, when five essays were published by evangelical scholars under the title The Openness of God. Recent theologians of note expressing this view include: Clark Pinnock, Greg Boyd, Thomas Jay Oord, John E. Sanders, Dallas Willard, Jürgen Moltmann, Richard Rice, C. Peter Wagner, John Polkinghorne, Hendrikus Berkhof, Adrio Konig, Harry Boer, Bethany Sollereder, Matt Parkins, Thomas Finger, W. Norris Clarke, Brian Hebblethwaite, Robert Ellis, Kenneth Archer Barry Callen, Henry Knight III, Gordon Olson, and Winkie Pratney. A significant, growing number of philosophers of religion affirm it: Peter Van Inwagen, Richard Swinburne, William Hasker, David Basinger, Nicholas Wolterstorff, Dean Zimmerman, Timothy O'Connor, James D. Rissler, Keith DeRose, Richard E. Creel, Robin Collins, J. R. Lucas, Vincent Brümmer,, Richard Purtill, Alan Rhoda, Jeffrey Koperski, Dale Tuggy, and Keith Ward. Biblical scholars Terence E. Fretheim, Karen Winslow, and John Goldingay affirm it. Others include writers Madeleine L'Engle and Paul C. Borgman, mathematician D.J. Bartholomew and biochemist/theologian Arthur Peacocke.Philosophical arguments
Open theists maintain that traditional classical theists hold the classical attributes of God together in an incoherent way. The main classical attributes are as follows:- All-good: God is the standard of moral perfection, all-benevolent, and perfectly loving.
- Simplicity: God has no parts, cannot be differentiated, and possesses no attribute as distinct from His being.
- Immutability: God cannot change in any respect.
- Impassibility: God cannot be affected by outside forces.
- Omnipresence: God is present everywhere, or more precisely, all things find their location in God.
- Omniscience: God knows absolutely everything: believes all truths and disbelieves all falsehoods. God's knowledge is perfect.
- Omnipotence: God can do anything because he is all-powerful and not limited by external forces.
Open theism also answers the question of how God can be blameless and omnipotent even though evil exists in the world. H. Roy Elseth gives an example of a parent that knows with certainty that his child would go out and murder someone if he was given a gun. Elseth argues that if the parent did give the gun to the child then the parent would be responsible for that crime. However, if God was unsure about the outcome then God would not be culpable for that act; only the one who committed the act would be guilty. This position is, however, dubious, as a parent who knows his child was probable, or likely, or even possibly going to shoot someone would be culpable; and God knew that it was likely that man would sin, and thus God is still culpable. An orthodox Christian might try, on the contrary, seek to ground a theodicy in the resurrection, both of Christ and the general resurrection to come, though this is not the traditional answer to evil.
Varieties of open theists
Philosopher Alan Rhoda has described several different approaches several open theists have taken with regard to the future and God's knowledge of it.- Voluntary Nescience: The future is alethically settled but nevertheless epistemically open for God because he has voluntarily chosen not to know truths about future contingents. It is thought Dallas Willard held this position.
- Involuntary Nescience: The future is alethically settled but nevertheless epistemically open for God because truths about future contingents are in principle unknowable. William Hasker, Peter Van Inwagen, and Richard Swinburne espouse this position.
- Non-Bivalentist Omniscience: The future is alethically open and therefore epistemically open for God because propositions about future contingents are neither true nor false. J. R. Lucas and Dale Tuggy espouse this position.
- Bivalentist Omniscience: The future is alethically open and therefore epistemically open for God because propositions asserting of future contingents that they 'will' obtain or that they 'will not' obtain are both false. Instead, what is true is that they 'might and might not' obtain. Greg Boyd holds this position."
Criticism
An open theist might respond that all such criticisms are misplaced. As to observation , it is not characteristic of open theists to say that the quest for something unchanging is bad. Indeed, open theists believe God's character is unchanging. As to observation , open theists do not characteristically say traditional forms of classical theism have exactly the same concept of God as the Greeks. Rather, they argue that they imported only some unbiblical assumptions from the Greeks. They also point to theologians of the Christian tradition who, throughout history, did not succumb so strongly to Hellenistic influences. As to observation , open theists do not argue that philosophical influences are bad in themselves. Rather, they argue that some philosophical influences on Christian theology are unbiblical and theologically groundless. Consider John Sanders' statement in The Openness of God :
Opponents of open theism, both Arminians, and Calvinists, such as John Piper, claim that the verses commonly used by open theists are anthropopathisms. They suggest that when God seems to change from action A to action B in response to prayer, action B was the inevitable event all along, and God divinely ordained human prayer as the means by which God actualized that course of events.
They also point to verses that suggest God is immutable, such as:
- : For I, the Lord, have not changed; and you, the sons of Jacob, have not reached the end.
- : God is not a man that He should lie, nor is He a mortal that He should repent. Would He say and not do, speak and not fulfill?
- : And also, the Strength of Israel will neither lie nor repent, for He is not a man to repent."
- : tell the end from the beginning, and from before, what was not done; say, 'My counsel shall stand, and all My desire I will do.'
Literary debate
In the early 18th century, an extended public correspondence flourished around the topic of open theism. The debate was incited by Samuel Fancourt's 1727 publication, The Greatness of Divine Love Vindicated. Over the next decade, four other English writers published polemical works in response. This led Fancourt to defend his views in six other publications. In his 1747 autobiography, in response to some who thought that this controversy had affected his career, Fancourt wrote, "Should it be suggested, that my religious principles were a prejudice unto me—I answer: so are those of every Dissenting Protestant in the Kingdom with some, if he dares to think and to speak what he thinks." Fancourt also names other writers who had supported his views.In 2005, a "raging debate" among evangelicals about "open or free-will theism" was in place. This period of controversy began in 1994 with the publication of The Openness of God. The debate between open and classical theists is illustrated by their books as in the following chart.
Year | Open theism books and comments | Classical theism books and comments |
1980 | – Rice was the "pioneer of contemporary evangelical open theism." | Critical acclaim, but public mostly unaware of open theism; the controversy had not yet begun. |
1989 | Critical acclaim, but public mostly unaware of open theism; the controversy had not yet begun. | |
1994 | – "ignited a firestorm of controversy." | "Provoked numerous hostile articles in academic and popular publications." The "conservative backlash" was "quick and fierce". |
1996 | – Considers divine omniscience, theodicy, and petitionary prayer in freewill perspective. | – Sees open theism as wrong biblically, theologically, and philosophically. |
1997 | – Made open theism the centerpiece of a theodicy. | – Asserts that open theism should be called new theism or neotheism because it is so different from classical theism. |
1998 | – “The most thorough standard presentation and defense of the openness view of God.” | – Accuses open theists of selective use of Scripture and caricaturing classical theism. |
2000 | – “The most passionate and articulate defense of openness theology to date.” – “A genuinely evangelical portrayal of the biblical God.” | – “The most influential critique of open theism.” |
2001 | – “A renewed defense of open theism” and a theodicy grounded in it. | – “Debate seemed to turn somewhat in favor of classical theism.” |
2002–2003 | – Attacked classical theists as "blueprint theologians" espousing a "blueprint world view". | – Attacked “open theism as theologically ruinous, dishonoring to God, belittling to Christ, and pastorally hurtful”. |
2004–2012 | – Contains appendix titled "Replies to my critics". | – Book's stated purpose is to “demonstrate the errors of open theism”. |
2013–2014 | – Argues that proponents of open theism have a right to be called “evangelical”. | – Declares that “open theists get God all wrong”. |
present | The Internet brought open theists and their debate with classical theists into public view. – An internet site supporting open theism is | The Internet brought classical theists and their debate with open theists into public view. Two internet sites supporting classical theism are: and |