Pathological (mathematics)
In mathematics, a pathological object is one which possesses deviant, irregular or counterintuitive property, in such a way that distinguishes it from what is conceived as a typical object in the same category. The opposite of pathological is well-behaved.
In analysis
A classic example of a pathological structure is the Weierstrass function, which is continuous everywhere but differentiable nowhere. The sum of a differentiable function and the Weierstrass function is again continuous but nowhere differentiable; so there are at least as many such functions as differentiable functions. In fact, by the Baire category theorem, one can show that continuous functions are generically nowhere differentiable.In layman's terms, the majority of functions are nowhere differentiable, and relatively few can ever be described or studied. In general, most useful functions also have some sort of physical basis or practical application, which means that they cannot be pathological at the level of hard mathematics or logic; aside from certain limiting cases like the delta distribution, they tend to be quite well-behaved and intuitive. To quote Henri Poincaré:
This highlights the fact that the term pathological is subjective, context-dependent, and subject to wearing off. Its meaning in any particular case resides in the community of mathematicians, and not necessarily within mathematics itself. Also, the quotation shows how mathematics often progresses via counter-examples to what is thought intuitive or expected. For instance, the "lack of derivatives" mentioned is intimately connected with current study of magnetic reconnection events in solar plasma.
In topology
One of the most notorious pathologies in topology is the Alexander horned sphere, a counterexample showing that topologically embedding the sphere S2 in R3 may fail to separate the space cleanly. As a counter-example, it motivated the extra condition of tameness, which suppresses the kind of wild behavior the horned sphere exhibits.Like many other pathologies, the horned sphere in a sense plays on infinitely fine, recursively generated structure, which in the limit violates ordinary intuition. In this case, the topology of an ever-descending chain of interlocking loops of continuous pieces of the sphere in the limit fully reflects that of the common sphere, and one would expect the outside of it, after an embedding, to work the same. Yet it does not: it fails to be simply connected.
For the underlying theory, see Jordan–Schönflies theorem.
Well-behaved
s very frequently speak of whether a mathematical object—a function, a set, a space of one sort or another—is "well-behaved". While the term has no fixed formal definition, it generally refers to the quality of satisfying a list of prevailing conditions, which might be dependent on context, mathematical interests, fashion, and taste. To ensure that an object is "well-behaved", mathematicians introduce further axioms to narrow down the domain of study. This has the benefit of making analysis easier, but produces a loss of generality of any conclusions reached. For example, non-Euclidean geometries were once considered to be ill-behaved, but have since become common objects of study from 19th century and onwards.In both pure and applied mathematics, well-behaved also means not violating any assumptions needed to successfully apply whatever analysis is being discussed.
The opposite case is usually labeled "pathological". It is not unusual to have situations in which most cases are pathological, but the pathological cases will not arise in practice—unless constructed deliberately.
The term "well-behaved" is generally applied in an absolute sense—either something is well-behaved or it is not. For example:
- In algorithmic inference, a well-behaved statistic is monotonic, well-defined, and sufficient.
- In Bézout's theorem, two polynomials are well-behaved, and thus the formula given by the theorem for the number of their intersections is valid, if their polynomial greatest common divisor is a constant.
- A meromorphic function is a ratio of two well-behaved functions, in the sense of those two functions being holomorphic.
- The Karush–Kuhn–Tucker conditions are first-order necessary conditions for a solution in a well-behaved nonlinear programming problem to be optimal; a problem is referred to as well-behaved if some regularity conditions are satisfied.
- In probability, events contained in the probability space's corresponding sigma-algebra are well-behaved, as are measurable functions.
- In calculus:
- *Analytic functions are better-behaved than general smooth functions.
- *Smooth functions are better-behaved than general differentiable functions.
- *Continuous differentiable functions are better-behaved than general continuous functions. The larger the number of times the function can be differentiated, the more well-behaved it is.
- *Continuous functions are better-behaved than Riemann-integrable functions on compact sets.
- *Riemann-integrable functions are better-behaved than Lebesgue-integrable functions.
- *Lebesgue-integrable functions are better-behaved than general functions.
- In topology, continuous functions are better-behaved than discontinuous ones.
- *Euclidean space is better-behaved than non-Euclidean geometry.
- *Attractive fixed points are better-behaved than repulsive fixed points.
- *Hausdorff topologies are better-behaved than those in arbitrary general topology.
- *Borel sets are better-behaved than arbitrary sets of real numbers.
- *Spaces with integer dimension are better-behaved than spaces with fractal dimension.
- In abstract algebra:
- *Groups are better-behaved than magmas and semigroups.
- *Abelian groups are better-behaved than non-Abelian groups.
- *Finitely-generated Abelian groups are better-behaved than non-finitely-generated Abelian groups.
- *-dimensional vector spaces are better-behaved than infinite-dimensional ones.
- *Fields are better-behaved than skew fields or general rings.
- *Separable field extensions are better-behaved than non-separable ones.
- *Normed division algebras are better-behaved than general composition algebras.
Pathological examples
- The discovery of irrational numbers by the school of Pythagoras in ancient Greece; for example, the length of the diagonal of a unit square, that is.
- The discovery of complex numbers in the 16th century in order to find the roots of cubic and quartic polynomial functions.
- The cardinality of the rational numbers is equal to the cardinality of the integers.
- Some number fields have rings of integers that do not form a unique factorization domain, for example the field.
- The discovery of fractals and other "rough" geometric objects.
- Weierstrass function, a real-valued function on the real line, that is continuous everywhere but differentiable nowhere.
- Test functions in real analysis and distribution theory, which are infinitely differentiable functions on the real line that are 0 everywhere outside of a given limited interval. An example of such a function is the test function,
- The Cantor set is a subset of the interval that has measure zero but is uncountable.
- The Peano space-filling curve is a continuous surjective function that maps the unit interval onto × .
- The Dirichlet function, which is the indicator function for rationals, is a bounded function that is not Riemann integrable.
- The Cantor function is a monotonic continuous surjective function that maps onto , but has zero derivative almost everywhere.
- Satisfaction classes containing "intuitively false" arithmetical statements can be constructed for countable, recursively saturated models of Peano arithmetic.
Whether a behavior is pathological is by definition subject to personal intuition. Pathologies depend on context, training, and experience, and what is pathological to one researcher may very well be standard behavior to another.
Pathological examples can show the importance of the assumptions in a theorem. For example, in statistics, the Cauchy distribution does not satisfy the central limit theorem, even though its symmetric bell-shape appears similar to many distributions which do; it fails the requirement to have a mean and standard deviation which exist and that are finite.
Some of the best-known paradoxes, such as Banach–Tarski paradox and Hausdorff paradox, are based on the existence of non-measurable sets. Mathematicians, unless they take the minority position of denying the axiom of choice, are in general resigned to living with such sets.
Computer science
In computer science, pathological has a slightly different sense with regard to the study of algorithms. Here, an input is said to be pathological if it causes atypical behavior from the algorithm, such as a violation of its average case complexity, or even its correctness. For example, hash tables generally have pathological inputs: sets of keys that collide on hash values. Quicksort normally has O time complexity, but deteriorates to O when it is given input that triggers suboptimal behavior.The term is often used pejoratively, as a way of dismissing such inputs as being specially designed to break a routine that is otherwise sound in practice. On the other hand, awareness of pathological inputs is important, as they can be exploited to mount a denial-of-service attack on a computer system. Also, the term in this sense is a matter of subjective judgment as with its other senses. Given enough run time, a sufficiently large and diverse user community, an input which may be dismissed as pathological could in fact occur.
Exceptions
A similar but distinct phenomenon is that of exceptional objects, which occurs when there are a "small" number of exceptions to a general pattern. By contrast, in cases of pathology, often most or almost all instances of a phenomenon are pathological.Subjectively, exceptional objects are generally considered "beautiful", unexpected examples of a theory, while pathological phenomena are often considered "ugly", as the name implies. Accordingly, theories are usually expanded to include exceptional objects. For example, the exceptional Lie algebras are included in the theory of semisimple Lie algebras: the axioms are seen as good, the exceptional objects as unexpected but valid.
By contrast, pathological examples are instead taken to point out a shortcoming in the axioms, requiring stronger axioms to rule them out. For example, requiring tameness of an embedding of a sphere in the Schönflies problem. In general, one may study the more general theory, including the pathologies, which may provide its own simplifications, but also the narrower theory, from which the original examples were drawn.