For all objects and, a category. The objects of this category are called 1-cells and its morphisms are called 2-cells; the composition in this category is usually written or and called vertical composition or composition along a 1-cell.
For all objects, and, there is a functor, called horizontal composition or composition along a 0-cell, which is associative and admits the identity 1 and 2-cells of as identities. Here, associativity for means that horizontally composing twice to is independent of which of the two and are composed first. The composition symbol is often omitted, the horizontal composite of 2-cells and being written simply as.
The notion of 2-category differs from the more general notion of a bicategory in that composition of 1-cells is required to be strictly associative, whereas in a bicategory it needs only be associative up to a 2-isomorphism. The axioms of a 2-category are consequences of their definition as Cat-enriched categories:
Vertical composition is associative and unital, the units being the identity 2-cells.
Horizontal composition is also associative and unital, the units being the identity 2-cells on the identity 1-cells.
The interchange law holds; i.e. it is true that for composable 2-cells
The interchange law follows from the fact that is a functor between hom categories. It can be drawn as a pasting diagram as follows: Here the left-hand diagram denotes the vertical composition of horizontal composites, the right-hand diagram denotes the horizontal composition of vertical composites, and the diagram in the centre is the customary representation of both.
Doctrines
In mathematics, a doctrine is simply a 2-category which is heuristically regarded as a system of theories. For example, algebraic theories, as invented by William Lawvere, is an example of a doctrine, as are multi-sorted theories, operads, categories, and toposes. The objects of the 2-category are called theories, the 1-morphisms are called models of the in, and the 2-morphisms are called morphisms between models. The distinction between a 2-category and a doctrine is really only heuristic: one does not typically consider a 2-category to be populated by theories as objects and models as morphisms. It is this vocabulary that makes the theory of doctrines worth while. For example, the 2-category Cat of categories, functors, and natural transformations is a doctrine. One sees immediately that all presheaf categories are categories of models. As another example, one may take the subcategory of Cat consisting only of categories with finiteproducts as objects and product-preserving functors as 1-morphisms. This is the doctrine of multi-sorted algebraic theories. If one only wanted 1-sorted algebraic theories, one would restrict the objects to only those categories that are generated under products by a single object. Doctrines were discovered by Jonathan Mock Beck.
Footnotes
Generalised algebraic models, by Claudia Centazzo.