Linguistic modality
In linguistics, modality is a system of linguistic options that allows for expressing a speaker's general intentions as well as the speaker's belief as to whether the proposition expressed is true, obligatory, desirable, or actual. Modal options can be realized by word order, modal auxiliaries and modal adjuncts.
Sometimes, the term mood is used to refer to both mood and modality; however, the two can be distinguished according to whether they refer to the grammatical expressions of various modalities or the meanings so expressed. Modality can also be considered equivalent to the idea of illocutionary force if the kinds of expressions which can express modal meanings also include lexical items such as performative verbs.
Modality is closely intertwined with other linguistic phenomena such as tense and aspect, evidentiality, conditionals, and others. As with other areas of linguistics, modality has been studied extensively from typological as well as formal perspectives.
Cross-linguistically, modality can be expressed by a variety of means, such as auxiliary verbs, verbal morphology or adverbs.
Typological approaches to modality usually favour a slightly wider definition of modality.
Linguistic modality, as outlined above, should not be confused with semiotic modality, a phenomenon also examined in the study of natural languages, for instance when comparing signed languages with spoken languages.
Expressions of modality
Classically, three categories of modality are distinguished in linguistics: epistemic, deontic and circumstantial modality. Epistemic modality is possibility and necessity relative to a speaker's knowledge, while deontic modality has to do with permissions and obligations according to some system of rules. Circumstantial modality is relative to the relevant circumstances of a conversation and in general dependent on facts of the world rather than the agent's knowledge. These different modalities can be expressed by auxiliaries such as 'must' or 'can', and can be illustrated in the English example below:The sentence in might be spoken by someone who has decided that all of the relevant facts in a particular murder investigation point to the conclusion that Agatha was the murderer, even though it may or may not actually be the case. The 'must' in this sentence thus expresses epistemic modality, for 'for all we know', Agatha must be the murderer - where 'for all we know' is relative to some knowledge the speakers possess. In contrast, might be spoken by someone who has decided that, according to some standard of conduct, Agatha has committed a vile crime, and therefore the correct course of action is to jail Agatha. The 'must' in sentence has neither an epistemic reading, nor a deontic reading. Rather, that Agatha must sneeze is relative to the relevant circumstances of the utterance. Although the English 'must' is ambiguous between these interpretations, the form of the other elements in the sentences helps to disambiguate.
In standard formal approaches to linguistic modality, an utterance expressing modality is one that can always roughly be paraphrased to fit the following template:
The set of propositions which forms the basis of evaluation is called the modal base. The result of the evaluation is called the modal force. For example, the utterance in expresses that, according to what the speaker has observed, it is necessary to conclude that John has a rather high income:
The modal base here is the knowledge of the speaker, the modal force is necessity. By contrast, could be paraphrased as ‘Given his abilities, the strength of his teeth, etc., it is possible for John to open a beer bottle with his teeth’. Here, the modal base is defined by a subset of John's abilities, the modal force is possibility.
Semantic accounts
Semantic approaches dealing with modality are traditionally based on the principles of modal logic. Both work with the notion that propositions can be mapped to sets of possible worlds; that is, a proposition can be defined as the set of worlds in which that proposition is true. For example, the proposition ‘the earth is flat’ corresponds to the set of possible worlds in which the earth is in fact flat.In this framework, modal expressions such as must and can are then analyzed as quantifiers over a set of possible worlds. This set of worlds is given by the modal base and is said to be the set of accessible worlds: For example, in sentence above, the modal base is the knowledge the speaker has in the actual world. Therefore, the set of accessible worlds is defined by the information the speaker has about John. Assume for example that the speaker knows that John just bought a new luxury car and has rented a huge apartment. The speaker also knows that John is an honest person with a humble family background and doesn't play the lottery. The set of accessible worlds is then the set of worlds in which all these propositions which the speaker knows about John are true.
The notions of necessity and possibility are then defined along the following lines: A proposition p follows necessarily from the set of accessible worlds, if all accessible worlds are part of p. Applied to the example in this would mean that in all the worlds which are defined by the speaker's knowledge about John, it is the case that John earns a lot of money.
In a similar way a proposition p is possible according to the set of accessible worlds, if some of these worlds are part of p.
Ways of expressing modality
Verbal morphology
In many languages modal categories are expressed by verbal morphology – that is, by alterations in the form of the verb. If these verbal markers of modality are obligatory in a language, they are called mood markers. Well-known examples of moods in some European languages are referred to as subjunctive, conditional and indicative as illustrated below with examples from French, all three with the verb avoir ‘to have’. As in most Standard European languages, the shape of the verb conveys not only information about modality, but also about other categories such as person and number of the subject.An example for a non-European language with a similar encoding of modality is Manam. Here, a verb is prefixed by a morpheme which encodes number and person of the subject. These prefixes come in two versions, one realis version and one irrealis version. Which one is chosen depends on whether the verb refers to an actual past or present event, or merely to a possible or imagined event.
Auxiliaries
Modal auxiliary verbs, such as the English words may, can, must, ought, will, shall, need, dare, might, could, would, and should, are often used to express modality, especially in the Germanic languages.Lexical expression
s such as "want" can be used to express modality lexically, as can adverbs.Other
Complementizers and conjunctions can be used to convey modality.Modal categories
Many different kinds of modal interpretations have been observed and studied, resulting in a variety of typologies. What follows below is one of the many ways that modality has been classified. Only broad categories have been distinguished below: the reader is referred to the main articles and the references for more detailed discussions.Realis vs. irrealis
The closely related realis, declarative, and evidential moods refer to situations that actually exist, are claimed to exist, or are inferred to exist. In contrast, irrealis moods refer to situations that are not known to exist. Two common irrealis moods are the conditional mood, stating what would happen under a certain condition or conditions, and the subjunctive mood, stating the speaker's preferences for what should occur or hypotheticals.Counterfactuals refer to things that are contrary to the actual situation. In English, counterfactuals can be expressed implicitly in "if"-clauses by using a tense form that normally refers to a time prior to the time actually semantically referred to in the if-clause. For example, If I knew that, I wouldn't have to ask contains the counterfactual If I knew, which refers to the present tense despite the form of the verb, and which denies the proposition "I know that". This contrasts with the construction If I know that,..., which is not a counterfactual because it means that maybe I know it and maybe I don't. Likewise, If I had known that, I would have gone there contains the counterfactual If I had known, denying the proposition that I had known.
Epistemic vs. deontic modality
Epistemic modals are used to indicate the possibility or necessity of some piece of knowledge. It deals with the likelihood of the actualization of the state of affairs. In the epistemic use, modals can be interpreted as indicating inference or some other process of reasoning involved in coming to the conclusion stated in the sentence containing the modal. However, epistemic modals do not necessarily require inference, reasoning, or evidence. One effect of using an epistemic modal is a general weakening of the speaker's commitment to the truth of the sentence containing the modal. However, it is disputed whether the function of modals is to indicate this weakening of commitment, or whether the weakening is a by-product of some other aspect of the modal's meaning.Examples of the expression of epistemic modality in English are: he might be there, He may be there, He should be there by now, and He must be there by now.
In contrast, deontic modality is concerned with possibility and necessity in terms of freedom to act. In other words, deontic modals state something about the desirability of the actualization of the state of affairs, expressed in varying degrees of obligation. English examples include She can go, You may go, You should go, and You must go. In English as in many other languages, some of the same words are used for deontic modality as for epistemic modality, and the meaning is distinguished from context: He must be there by now versus He must be there tomorrow at noon.