Presupposition
In the branch of linguistics known as pragmatics, a presupposition is an implicit assumption about the world or background belief relating to an utterance whose truth is taken for granted in discourse. Examples of presuppositions include:
- Jane no longer writes fiction.
- * Presupposition: Jane once wrote fiction.
- Have you stopped eating meat?
- * Presupposition: you had once eaten meat.
- Have you talked to Hans?
- * Presupposition: Hans exists.
Crucially, negation of an expression does not change its presuppositions: I want to do it again and I don't want to do it again both presuppose that the subject has done it already one or more times; My wife is pregnant and My wife is not pregnant both presuppose that the subject has a wife. In this respect, presupposition is distinguished from entailment and implicature. For example, The president was assassinated entails that The president is dead, but if the expression is negated, the entailment is not necessarily true.
Negation of a sentence containing a presupposition
If presuppositions of a sentence are not consistent with the actual state of affairs, then one of two approaches can be taken. Given the sentences My wife is pregnant and My wife is not pregnant when one has no wife, then either:- Both the sentence and its negation are false; or
- Strawson's approach: Both "my wife is pregnant" and "my wife is not pregnant" use a wrong presupposition and therefore can not be assigned truth values.
- "There exists exactly one person, who is my wife and who is not pregnant"
- "There does not exist exactly one person, who is my wife and who is pregnant."
Projection of presuppositions
A presupposition of a part of an utterance is sometimes also a presupposition of the whole utterance, and sometimes not. For instance, the phrase my wife triggers the presupposition that I have a wife. The first sentence below carries that presupposition, even though the phrase occurs inside an embedded clause. In the second sentence, however, it does not. John might be mistaken about his belief that I have a wife, or he might be deliberately trying to misinform his audience, and this has an effect on the meaning of the second sentence, but, perhaps surprisingly, not on the first one.- John thinks that my wife is beautiful.
- John said that my wife is beautiful.
Here, the presupposition triggered by the expression my wife is blocked, because it is stated in the antecedent of the conditional: That sentence doesn't imply that I have a wife. In the following example, it is not stated in the antecedent, so it is allowed to project, i.e. the sentence does imply that I have a wife.
Hence, conditional sentences act as filters for presuppositions that are triggered by expressions in their consequent.
A significant amount of current work in semantics and pragmatics is devoted to a proper understanding of when and how presuppositions project.
Presupposition triggers
A presupposition trigger is a lexical item or linguistic construction which is responsible for the presupposition, and thus "triggers" it. The following is a selection of presuppositional triggers following Stephen C. Levinson's classic textbook on Pragmatics, which in turn draws on a list produced by Lauri Karttunen. As is customary, the presuppositional triggers themselves are italicized, and the symbol » stands for 'presupposes'.Definite descriptions
Definite descriptions are phrases of the form "the X" where X is a noun phrase. The description is said to be proper when the phrase applies to exactly one object, and conversely, it is said to be improper when either there exist more than one potential referents, as in "the senator from Ohio", or none at all, as in "the king of France". In conventional speech, definite descriptions are implicitly assumed to be proper, hence such phrases trigger the presupposition that the referent is unique and existent.In Western epistemology, there is a tradition originating with Plato of defining knowledge as justified true belief. On this definition, for someone to know X, it is required that X be true. A linguistic question thus arises regarding the usage of such phrases: does a person who states "John knows X" implicitly claim the truth of X? Steven Pinker explored this question in a popular science format in a 2007 book on language and cognition, using a widely publicized example from a speech by a U.S. president. A 2003 speech by George W. Bush included the line, "British Intelligence has learned that Saddam Hussein recently sought significant quantities of uranium from Africa." Over the next few years, it became apparent that this intelligence lead was incorrect. But the way the speech was phrased, using a factive verb, implicitly framed the lead as truth rather than hypothesis. There is however a strong alternative view that factivity thesis, the proposition that relational predicates having to do with knowledge, such as knows, learn, remembers, and realized, presuppose the factual truth of their object, is incorrect.
- Martha regrets drinking John's home brew.
- * Presupposition: Martha did in fact drink John's home brew.
- Frankenstein was aware that Dracula was there.
- * Presupposition: Dracula was in fact there.
- John realized that he was in debt.
- * Presupposition: John was in fact in debt.
- It was odd how proud he was.
- * Presupposition: He was in fact proud.
Implicative verbs
- John managed to open the door.
»John tried to open the door. - John forgot to lock the door.
»John ought to have locked, or intended to lock, the door.
Change of state or continuation of state verbs
With these presupposition triggers, the current unfolding situation is considered presupposed information.- John stopped teasing his wife.
»John had been teasing his wife. - Joan began teasing her husband.
»Joan hadn't been teasing her husband.
Iteratives
These types of triggers presuppose the existence of a previous state of affairs.- The flying saucer came again.
»The flying saucer came before. - You can't get gobstoppers anymore.
»You once could get gobstoppers. - Carter returned to power.
»Carter held power before.
Temporal clauses
The situation explained in a clause that begins with a temporal clause constructor is typically considered backgrounded information.- Before Strawson was even born, Frege noticed presuppositions.
»Strawson was born. - While Chomsky was revolutionizing linguistics, the rest of social science was asleep.
»Chomsky was revolutionizing linguistics. - Since Churchill died, we've lacked a leader.
»Churchill died.
Cleft sentences
Cleft sentence structures highlight particular aspects of a sentence and consider the surrounding information to be backgrounded knowledge. These sentences are typically not spoken to strangers, but rather to addressees who are aware of the ongoing situation.- Cleft construction: It was Henry that kissed Rosie.
»Someone kissed Rosie. - Pseudo-cleft construction: What John lost was his wallet.
»John lost something.Comparisons and contrasts
- Marianne called Adolph a male chauvinist, and then HE insulted HER.
»For Marianne to call Adolph a male chauvinist would be to insult him. - Carol is a better linguist than Barbara.
»Barbara is a linguist.Counterfactual conditionals
- If the notice had only said 'mine-field' in Welsh as well as in English, we would never have lost poor Llewellyn.
»The notice didn't say 'mine-field' in Welsh.Questions
- Is there a professor of linguistics at MIT?
»Either there is a professor of linguistics at MIT or there isn't. - Is Newcastle in England or in Australia?
»Newcastle is in England or Newcastle is in Australia. - Who is the professor of linguistics at MIT?
»Someone is the professor of linguistics at MIT.Possessive case
- John's children are very noisy.
»John has children.Accommodation of presuppositions
But that presupposition, as stated, is completely trivial, given what we know about New York. Several million people had dinner in New York last night, and that in itself doesn't satisfy the presupposition of the sentence. What is needed for the sentence to be felicitous is really that somebody relevant to the interlocutors had dinner in New York last night, and that this has been mentioned in the previous discourse, or that this information can be recovered from it. Presupposition triggers that disallow accommodation are called anaphoric presupposition triggers.
Presupposition in critical discourse analysis
is a broad study belonging to not one research category. It focuses on identifying presuppositions of an abstract nature from varying perspectives. CDA is considered critical, not only in the sense of being analytical, but also in the ideological sense.Through the analysis of written texts and verbal speech, Teun A. van Dijk says CDA studies power imbalances existing in both the conversational and political spectrum. With the purpose of first identifying and then tackling inequality in society, van Dijk describes CDA as a nonconformist piece of work. One notable feature of ideological presuppositions researched in CDA is a concept termed synthetic personalisation
Logical construct
To describe a presupposition in the context of propositional calculus and truth-bearers, Belnap defines "A sentence is a presupposition of a question if the truth of the sentence is a necessary condition of the question's having some true answer." Then referring to the semantic theory of truth, interpretations are used to formulate a presupposition: "Every interpretation which makes the question truly answerable is an interpretation which makes the presupposed sentence true as well."A sentence that expresses a presupposition in a question may be characterized as follows: the question has some true answer if and only if the sentence is true.